Infra-Domain Proofs 2
post by Diffractor · 2021-03-28T09:15:15.284Z · LW · GW · 0 commentsContents
No comments
Lemma 7: For s.t. and , and , and is compact, LHC, and second-countable, then . The same result holds for .
This is the only spot where we need that is LHC and not merely locally compact.
Here's how it's going to work. We're going to use the details of the proof of Theorem 2 to craft two special functions and of a certain form, which exceed and . Then, of course, as a result. We'll then show that can be written as the supremum of finitely many functions in (or ) which all approximate , so , establishing that .
From our process of constructing a basis for the function space back in Theorem 2, we have a fairly explicit method of crafting a directed set of approximating functions for and . The only approximator functions you need to build any are step functions of the form with being a finite rational number, and being selected from the base of , and where is our compact hull operator. Any function of this form approximates , and taking arbitrary suprema of them, itself is produced.
Since functions of this form (and suprema of finite collections of them) make a directed set with a supremum of or above ( or above, respectively), we can isolate a from the directed set of basis approximators for , s.t. , because . And similarly, we can isolate a which approximates s.t. , because .
Now, it's worthwhile to look at the exact form of and . Working just with (all the same stuff works for ), it's a finite supremum of atomic step functions, so
and, by how our atomic step functions of the directed set associated with were built, we know that for all i, . (remember, the are selected from the base, so we can take the compact hull of them).
There's a critical split here between the behavior of the type signature, and the type signature.
For the type signature, there's finitely many i, and everything not in the gets mapped to . Since , and is compact, is bounded below (Lemma 1), so for this finite supremum to exceed , the must cover .
For the type signature, again there's finitely many i, but we can't guarantee that the cover , because everything not in some gets mapped to 0, and might not be bounded above 0. So, we'll add in a "dummy" step function . This is just the constant-0 function, which approximates everything, so nothing changes. However, it ensures that is indeed covered by the open sets of the finite collection of step functions.
So... Given that we have our , what does the function look like? Well, it looks like
We could do this in the case from adding in the "dummy" open sets to get the family and family to both cover .
Anyways, equals . There's finitely many i's and finitely many j's by how g and g' were built, so this is a supremum of finitely many atomic step functions. Since , if we can just show that all these atomic step functions are approximators for in (or ), then (supremum of finitely many approximators is an approximator), and we'd show our desired result that . So let's get started on showing that, regardless of and ,
Now, if , then this function maps everything to or 0, which trivially approximates . Otherwise, everything in gets mapped to , and everything not in it gets mapped to (or 0)
We know by our process of construction for this that and , so let's try to work with that. Well, for the case. The case is a bit more delicate since we added those two dummy functions. We have:
The first strict inequality was because of what and were. Then, just move the constants in. For the first non-strict inquality, it's because of monotonicity for our compact hull operator, , so it has a smaller compact hull. Then the next inequality is just grouping the two infs, and we're finished.
At this point, the usual argument of "fix a directed set of functions ascending up to , for each patch of you can find a function from your directed set that beats the value on that spot, this gets you an open cover of , it's compact, isolate a finite subcover ie finitely many functions, take an upper bound in your directed set, bam, it beats the step function on a compact superset of its open set so it beats the step function, and the directed set was arbitrary so is approximated by the atomic step function" from Theorem 2 kicks in, to show that the atomic step function approximates . Since this works for arbitrary , and there are finitely many of these, the finite supremum approximates , and dominates , and we're done.
Now for the case. This case works perfectly fine if our pair has and being above 0. But what if our has being above 0, but our j index is picking that "dummy" approximator? Or vice-versa. Or maybe they're both the "dummy" approximator.
That last case can be disposed of, because is just the constant-0 function, which trivially approximates everything. That leaves the case where just one of the step functions isn't the constant-0 function. Without loss of generality, assume is paired with , but the other one is the "dummy" approximator. Then our goal is to show that . This can be done because, since , and , we have
And the rest of the argument works with no problems from there.
Lemma 8: If , and , then , provided lies in the function space of interest. (or ), and is compact, LHC, and second-countable.
By our constructions in Theorem 2, we can always write any function as the supremum of atomic step functions below it, , as long as . Since , we can find finitely many atomic step functions which all approximate s.t. the function exceeds . In the case, since the finite supremum exceeds , which is bounded below by Lemma 1, the family covers .
Now, consider the finite collection of atomic step functions . If we can show that all of these approximate , and the supremum of them is larger than , then, since the supremum of finitely many approximators is an approximator, we'll have shown that , establishing approximation. So, let's show those. For arbitrary , we have
So these atomic step functions all approximate . For exceeding , we have, for arbitrary ,
And so, our result follows. It's possible that, for the case, lies in no , but then the supremum of the empty set would be 0, and since the supremum of the exceeds , as well, so the same inequality holds.
Lemma 9: If and with with being compact, LHC, and second-countable, then .
We can invoke Theorem 2, to write any function as the supremum of atomic step functions below it, , as long as . Since , we can find finitely many atomic step functions which all approximate s.t. the function exceeds . Also, is bounded below by Lemma 1, so the finite family covers the entire space.
Now, consider the finite collection of atomic step functions . If we can show that all of these approximate , and the supremum of them is larger than , then, since the supremum of finitely many approximators is an approximator, we'll have shown that , establishing approximation. So, let's show those. For arbitrary , we have
So these atomic step functions all approximate . For exceeding , we have, for arbitrary ,
And so, our result follows.
Lemma 10: If and with with being compact, LHC, and second-countable, then for all , , as long as is also bounded in .
By Theorem 2, we can always write any function as the supremum of atomic step functions below it, , where . Since , we can find finitely many atomic step functions which all approximate s.t. the function exceeds .
Now, consider the following finite finite collection of atomic step functions. , along with
If we can show that all of these approximate , and the supremum of them is larger than , then, since the supremum of finitely many approximators is an approximator, we'll have shown that , establishing approximation. So, let's show those.
For arbitrary , if , then we have
So these atomic step functions all approximate . If , then the atomic step function turns into , which also approximates .
For the one extra step function we're adding in, we have two possible cases. One is where , the other one is where . In such a case, the function turns into c_{0}, which trivially approximates . However, if , then we have
For any , so this constant strictly undershoots the minimal value of across the whole space, and thus approximates by Lemma 2.
So, this finite collection of functions has its supremum being an approximator of . Now for showing that the supremum beats . If lies in some , then
And we've shown that this supremum of step functions beats our new function. If lies in none of the , then the original supremum of step functions must have mapped to 0, and that beats , so . That's the only possible thing that could have happened. Then
So, this case is taken care of too, and our supremum of step functions beats . The lemma then finishes up, we have that implies that for any and s.t. and and all lie in , we have
NOW we can begin proving our theorems!
Theorem 4: The subset of (or ) consisting of inframeasures is an -BC domain when is compact, second-countable, and LHC.
This proof will begin by invoking either Corollary 1 or Proposition 6. Since locally hull-compact implies locally compact, we can invoke these, to get that , or is an -BC domain with a top element.
Then, if we can just show that the set of inframeasures is closed under directed suprema and arbitrary nonempty infinima, we can invoke Theorem 3 to get that the space of -inframeasures (or -inframeasures) is an -BC domain. This is the tricky part.
For our conventions on working with infinity, we'll adopt the following. 0 times any number in is 0. Infinity times any number in is infinity. Infinity plus any number in is infinity. Given two functions bounded below, then is the function which maps to , which is always continuous when are, due to being monotone, and preserving directed suprema. The distance between points in , for defining the distance between functions as is the usual distance when both numbers are finite, 0 when both numbers are and when one point is and the other isn't.
An inframeasure is a function in or with the following three properties.
should be 1-Lipschitz, it should map the constant-0 function to 0 or higher, and it should be convex.
The definition of 1-Lipschitzness is that, using using our convention for the distance between points in and the distance between functions , we have that for any two functions, .
The definition of concavity is that, for all ,,
Admittedly, this might produce situations where we're adding infinity and negative infinity, which we haven't defined yet, but this case is ruled out by Lemma 3 and Lemma 1. Any function has a finite lower bound by Lemma 1, and Lemma 3 steps in to ensure that they must have a finite expectation value according to . So, we'll never have to deal with cases where we're adding negative infinity to something, we're working entirely in the realm of real numbers plus infinity.
Now, let's get started on showing that the directed supremum of 1-Lipschitz, concave functions which map 0 upwards is 1-Lipschitz, concave, and maps 0 upwards.
Let's start with 1-Lipschitzness. In the case that our functions have a distance of infinity from each other, 1-Lipschitness is trivially fulfilled. So we can assume that have a finite distance from each other. Observe that it's impossible that (without loss of generality) is infinity, while is finite. This is because we have
So, if that first term is infinite, we can find which map arbitrarily high. And then would only be a constant away, so the values would climb arbitrarily high as well, making be infinite as well. Then we'd have
And this would also show 1-Lipschitzness. So now we arrive at our last case where is finite and the directed suprema are both finite. Then we'd have
and we're done. That was just unpacking definitions, and then the was because we can upper-bound the distance between the suprema of the two sets of numbers by the maximum distance between points paired off with each other. Then just apply 1-Lipschitzness at the end.
As for concavity, it's trivial when p=0 or 1, because then (for as an example)
So now, let's start working on the case where isn't 0 or 1. We have
First equality is just unpacking definitions. Second equality is because, if the directed supremum is unbounded above, multiplying by a finite constant and taking the directed supremum still gets you to infinity, and it also works for the finite constants. Then, we observe that for any chosen by the first directed supremum and chosen by the second, we can take an upper bound of the two to exceed the value. Conversely, any particular can be used for both directed suprema. So we can move the directed suprema to the outside. Then we just apply concavity, and pack back up.
Finally, there's mapping 0 to above 0. This is easy.
All these proofs work equally well with both type signatures, so in both type signatures, the set of inframeausures is closed under directed suprema.
Now we'll show they're closed under unbounded infinima. This is the super-hard part. First up, 1-Lipschitzness.
1-Lipschitzness is trivial if , so we can assume that this value is finite. It's also trivial if , because then the distance is 0. So we can assume that one of these values is finite. Without loss of generality, let's say that . Then, we can go:
Via Lemma 3. Now, at this point, we're going to need to invoke either Lemma 5 for the case, or Lemma 6 for the case. We'll treat the two cases identically by using the terminology . In the case, this is just , because the functions have a finite lower bound via compactness/Lemma 1, and we're in the assumed case where . In the case, it's , which is a different sort of function. Anyways, since we have , this then means that by Lemma 5 or 6 (as the type signature may be). So, swapping out the supremum over with choosing a and evaluating the , makes that second directed supremum go down in value, so the value of the equation as a whole go up. So, in both cases, we have
The starting inequality was already extensively discussed. Then, the shift to the absolute value is because we know the quantity as a whole is positive. The gap between the two suprema is upper-bounded by the maximum gap between the two terms with the same chosen. Similarly, the gap between thetwo infinima is upper-bounded by the maximum gap between the two terms with the same chosen. Then we just do a quick conversion to distance, and apply 1-Lipschitzness of all the we're taking the infinimum of. Continuing onwards, we have
Now, we've got two possibilities. The first case is where has range in . In such a case, the latter term would turn into , so the contents as a whole of the absolute value would be . The second case is where has range in . In such a case, the latter term would be as close or closer to than , so we can upper-bound the contents of the absolute-value chunk by . In both cases, we have
And we're done, 1-Lipschitzness is preserved under arbitrary infinima, for both type signatures.
Now for concavity. Concavity is trivial when or , so let's assume , letting us invoke Lemma 7. Let's show concavity. We have
The first equality was just unpacking via Lemma 3. Then we can move the constant in, group into a single big directed supremum, combine the infs (making the inside bigger), then apply concavity for all our . Now it gets interesting. Since and and we have that by Lemma 7. Since all possible choices make an approximator for , we can go...
And concavity is shown. The proof works equally well for both type signatures.
All that remains is showing that the constant-0 function maps to 0 or higher, which is thankfully, quite easy, compared to concavity and 1-Lipschitzness. This is automatic for the case, so we'll just be dealing with the other type signature.
Remember our result back in Lemma 2 that if you have a constant function where , then . We'll be using that. Also we'll be using Lemma 4 that no 1-Lipschitz function mapping to 0 or higher can map a function any lower than , which is finite, by Lemma 1. So, we have
And we're done. First equality was just the usual unpacking of infinite inf via Lemma 3, second one was because, if , then , so the function value goes down, and the third inequality was because none of the can map below since . That's it!
Now, since the space of inframeasures (concave, 1-Lipschitz, weakly-normalized) is closed under directed sup and arbitrary inf in and , we can invoke Theorem 3 to conclude that it makes an -BC domain.
Theorem 5: The following properties are all preserved under arbitrary infinima and directed supremum for both and -inframeasures, if is compact, second-countable, and LHC.
(supernormalization)
(homogenity)
(cohomogenity)
(C-additivity)
(crispness)
So, the deal with this proof is that the directed suprema part works equally well for both cases, but the arbitrary infinima part will need to be done once for the type signature (where it's marginally easier), and done a second way for the case, where it's considerably more difficult to accomplish.
First, .
Second, .
Third, .
Fourth, , which is trivial from second and third.
Fifth, supernormalization.
Sixth, homogenity.
Seventh, cohomogenity.
Eighth, C-additivity.
Ninth, crispness, which follows from six and eight since crispnes is equivalent to the conjunction of homogenity and c-additivity.
Now for arbitrary infinima in the case. We'll note when the same proof works for the case, and when we have to loop back later with a more sophisticated argument. Lemma 3 is used throughout.
First, preservation of under infinima. We already know that, by being preserved under arbitrary infinima it can't be below 0, so that leaves showing that it can't be above 0.
This was by monotonicity, since , and then we just apply that . This proof works for the type signature.
Second, preservation of under infinima. Since when via Lemma 2, we can go
And we're done. In order, that was unpacking the arbitrary inf, the inequality was because we swapped out for a more restricted class of approximators (value decreases), then we reexpressed , applied concavity (value decreases), distributed the inf in (value decreases), used that always, and our assumption that (value decreases), and then we can finish up easily. Same proof works just as well for the type signature.
Third, preservation of under infinima. Since when by Lemma 2, we can go
(
Due to monotonicity. Same proof works for the type signature.
Fourth, preservation of under infinima. This is trivial since we proved preservation of and under infinima already, for both type signatures.
For 5, supernormalization is that for all numbers in or respectively. We'll show this is preserved under infinima. We have to prove both directions of this separately. In one direction, we have
Which establishes an upper bound. For a lower bound, we have, since implies by Lemma 2,
Now, for the type signature, the only fiddly bit is the lower-bound argument, because maybe . In that case, you can just apply the fact that is preserved under infinima, which we proved already.
Number 6: Homogenity, that for any , . We only need to check , because for , it's saying that , which we've already shown is preserved under arbitrary infinima. This will work equally well for both type signatures.
And now, if , then . And similarly, if , then , by Lemma 8. So, we can switch to taking approximants of itself and scaling them, because every approximant of , scaled by , is an approximant of . And every approximant of , scaled by , is an approximant of . Due to this, we have
And then we can go, by homogenity,
And so, homogenity is preserved under arbitrary infinima, for both type signatures.
Seventh, preservation of cohomogenity under infinima. The condition is , for functions s.t. is lower-semicontinuous, and . This holds for as well, in both type signatures, because then it's just , which we've already shown is preserved under arbitrary infinima.
This is exceptionally difficult to show in the type signature, so we'll just show it for the type signature for now and circle back to it at the end.
Now things get tricky. First, observe that if , then
By appealing to Lemma 8, then 9. And then, adding to both sides which preserves the approximation by Lemma 9, we'd have
And we can also get a converse to this. If , then, by Lemma 8,
And then, adding to both sides with Lemma 9, we'd get
So, given that we can shift approximants back and forth between and freely, we can get
And then, since rewrites as , we can go
(by cohomogenity) and then rewrite as
And we're done, cohomogenity has been proved to be preserved under arbitrary inf for the type signature. The proof is substantially trickier.
Eighth, preservation of C-additivity under infinima. The condition is for all constants . Again, this is one we'll have to just prove for the type signature, and not the type signature, as that one takes more work to show. We can start with showing
Now, observe that if , then
By adding a constant and appealing to Lemma 9. And we can also get a converse to this. If , then, by Lemma 9,
So, given that we can shift approximants back and forth between and freely, we can get
And C-additivity is preserved under arbitrary infinima.
That just leaves condition 9, preservation of crispness under infinima. Crispness is, for all , , . This is equivalent to the conjunction of C-additivity and homogenity, both of which are preserved under arbitrary infinima, so the same applies to crispness as well. Accordingly, we don't need to prove this a second time for , because it will follow for free when we prove that C-additivity is preserved under infinima in the case.
Time for the two last difficult cases, showing preservation of cohomogenity under arbitrary infinima for the type signature, and doing the same for C-additivity.
For cohomogenity, we want the following to be preserved under infinima.
for functions s.t. is lower-semicontinuous, and . What we'll do is just prove it for the case where and are both bounded above 0.
Once we get this case, we can consider making an arbitrarily small perturbation of our function if one of those two conditions is violated, in order to apply the exact cohomogenity result, and then 1-Lipschitzness (applied to the arbitrary closeness of the perturbed function and the actual function) can be used to show that the cohomogenity equality comes arbitrarily close to holding since the equality holds exactly for the perturbation, so the equality also works for cases where one of the two functions may be 0 in places.
To do this, since the result is trivial for , we'll prove if . Then we'll use concavity (preserved under arbitrary infinima) to get the other inequality direction, and show the cohomogenity equality if . Then we'll use further arguments to show that if the equality holds for , it also holds for .
So, assume , and we'll show one inequality direction of cohomogenity.
Observe that if , then
by Lemma 8. And then, applying Lemma 10,
Now, the important thing here is that must be bounded above , otherwise wouldn't be bounded above 0, which we're assuming. Then, since a possible approximator to would be (for sufficiently small that still undershoots the lower bound of ), the directed supremum of approximators to does contain some s.t. is never below 0 and thus is a legit function. Such a suitable would be , because would equal , which is strictly above 0 because by assumption.
Thus, if we're taking the directed supremum of , we're guaranteed to have some functions where, instead of having
as Lemma 10 says, we can replace it with
Because there are suitably high s.t. the lower bound never becomes relevant.
Anyways, after all these details, we can go
Because those things in of the second line are a subset of all the stuff that approximates . Now, we can apply 1-Lipschitzness to get
And then rewrite a bit and apply cohomogenity for the to get
And then, since we have
but can be arbitrarily small, we get
Which is one inequality direction of cohomogenity. But it's proved only for . Assuming , let's derive the other direction from concavity, known to be preserved under arbitrary infinima.
This is just rewriting things. Since we're assuming , is a suitable number to use for mixing things together so we can apply concavity. We apply concavity, yielding
Now, cohomogenity for the various implies that . We know that is preserved under arbitary inf, we proved it already. So we can rewrite our previous concavity line as
and then simplify to yield
And so we've derived
the other direction of the inequality. So cohomogenity holds for , and when the various functions are bounded away from zero. Now, using that it holds for , we'll prove it for arbitrary . Let now. Then we can go
Deriving cohomogenity for the case, because we can apply cohomogenity to since that's above 1, and cohomogenity works in that case.
So cohomogenity is preserved overall under arbitrary infinima, as long as the functions are bounded away from 0. Then you can just use a limiting argument with the 1-Lipschitz constant to extend to functions that touch 0.
Time for our last piece, preservation of C-additivity under infinima. The condition is for all constants . The way this will work is we'll show it for (the case is trivial), and then use that to show it for . So, assume
Now, observe that if , then
By adding a constant and appealing to Lemma 10. There are always approximants of this form above zero, because so we can just take to be sufficiently small. So, we get
By going to a smaller collection of approximants, then applying 1-Lipschitzness. Anyways, since is arbitrarily small, we have
And to show equality, observe that if we had a strict > sign for some , we'd get a violation of 1-Lipschitzness, since and are only distance apart, but our inframeasure (which is 1-Lipschitz) would have the two functions being more than apart from each other.
Now that it's proven for , let's prove it for . We have
Because we can apply C-additivity to . Now it's proven in full generality.
That's the last of it, pretty much every nice condition we could ask for is preserved under finite suprema and arbitrary infinima.
Proposition 7: The functor mapping to and to is indeed a functor .
So, first-up, we already know that a space of inframeasures over an -BC domain is an -BC domain by Corollary 1 and Theorem 4 so the objects work out, we don't need to worry about this part.
Second, we'll need to show that is indeed a legit inframeasure if is.
Third, we'll need to show that is not just a function , it's also a continuous function, showing that said maybe-functor indeed maps morphisms to morphisms .
And finally, we'll need to show that said maybe-functor preserves identity morphisms and morphism composition in order to show it's a functor.
Starting on that second part (first part is taken care of), the requirements for
to be an inframeasure are Scott-continuity (monotone, and preserving suprema of directed subsets), 1-Lipschitzness, mapping the constant-0 function up, and concavity.
For monotonicity, if , then, by the definition of pushforward, and being monotone (since it's an inframeasure), we have
And monotonicity of is shown.
For preservation of directed suprema, letting be a directed set of Scott-continous functions , we have
And we're done. The first equality was just reexpressing definitions, then we reexpress the function, use continuity of to shift the directed suprema to the outside, and wrap the definition back up.
For 1-Lipschitzness of , we have
And this is shown. We just used definitions of pushforward, then 1-Lipschitzness of and how distances between functions work, then one last inequality and everything works.
For mapping 0 above 0, we have
And finally, for concavity,
Where we used concavity of for the inequality, and then definitions.
So, indeed, is always a legit inframeasure. and was arbitrary, so this shows our functor always maps morphisms between domains to functions between inframeasures over domains. The various other properties like C-additivity and such can be shown if the reader wishes it, they're all pretty simple to show, if you want a more restricted version of this functor.
We do need to show that is a continuous function to show that said maybe-functor maps morphisms to morphisms. So, we need monotonicity and preservation of directed suprema of inframeasures.
Assume . Then
And was arbitrary, so
And thus, is indeed a monotone function, regardless of . Time to show preservation of directed suprema. Let be a directed set of inframeasures in . We have
First equality was using the definition of , second equality was using that were continuous so their composition was continuous, and how directed suprema of continuous functions (the ) works. Then there's just a bit of reexpressing with the definition of , and writing it as a directed suprema of inframeasures. And was an arbitrary continuous function (or ), so we have
And thus, is indeed continuous, since it preserves suprema of directed sets.
Now that we know it maps objects to objects and morphisms to morphisms, we need to check that said maybe-functor preserves identity morphisms and morphism composition.
For identity morphisms, we have
Now, was arbitrary, so we have
And was arbitrary, so we have . That's preservation of identity morphisms down.
Now for preservation of composition. Let , , , and .
Since was arbitrary, we have
And so, since was arbitrary, we have
Therefore, the functor mapping spaces to their spaces of inframeasures, and functions to their pushforwards is indeed a functor.
Proposition 8: The "space of inframeasures" functor is locally continuous.
Inspired by Lemma 5.2.2 and Definition 5.2.3 from Abramsky, we must check local continuity of the functor. In particular, we must show that the function
is continuous. This is done by showing monotonicity and preservation of directed suprema. First up is monotonicity. If , then
That inequality in the middle was, because , then , and is Scott-continuous, and all Scott-continuous functions are monotone. Since was arbitrary, we have and since was arbitrary, we have , establishing monotonicity.
Time for establishing preservation of directed suprema. Let be a directed set of functions . Then
We use continuity of functions a few times here, like continuity of to move the directed supremum out of the inside. Now, since was arbitrary, we have
And, since was arbitrary, we have
Which is precisely the continuity of the function which maps a function to its pushforward, and local continuity is established. This can be seen by using the notation instead of , because then it's
Which is more clearly preservation of directed suprema of functions.
Proposition 9: The category of -BC domains is closed under lifting, ,,,, function space, strict function space, and bilimit.
We'll show that given three basic results, we can derive the entire theorem from results in Abramsky and stuff we've already proved. Our three basic results we'll need to show are that:
1: If is an -BC domain, then is bounded-complete and has a countable basis.
2: If are -BC domains, then is bounded-complete and has a countable basis.
3: If are -BC domains, then has a countable basis.
Assuming these three results work out, we can show the entire theorem, as follows.
For lifting, the table in Summary 3.2.6 indicates that lifting a continuous domain produces a continuous domain, so all that remains is showing bounded-completeness and the existence of a countable basis, to establish that lifting an -BC domain produces an -BC domain. (Our first thing we need to show)
For coalesced sum , the table in Summary 3.2.6 indicates that coalesced sum of continuous domains is a continuous domain, so all that remains is showing bounded-completeness and the existence of a countable basis to establish that coalesced sum of -BC domains is an -BC domain. (Our second thing we need to show)
For sum , because and -BC domains are closed under lifting and coalesced sum, they're also closed under sum.
For product , Corollary 4.1.6 says that the category BC is cartesian-closed, so we at least know that is a BC-domain. Then, Proposition 3.2.4.2 says that a basis for is the product of the bases for and . Both of these are countable, so has a countable basis, and so it's an -BC domain.
For smash product , happens to be a retraction of . Just map all the and pairs in to , and the pairs to themselves. This is Scott-continuous, and the corresponding Scott-continuous section is just the obvious injection.
-BC domains are closed under product. And, Proposition 4.1.3 says that BC-domains are closed under retracts, so we know that is at least a BC-domain. All that remains to check is that has a countable basis. This follows by Lemma 3.1.3, that the retraction of the countable basis for is a basis for .
For function space, Proposition 4.1.5 says that the category of BC-domains is closed under function space, so we at least know that is a BC-domain. Then, it has a countable basis (the third thing we need to show), so it's an -BC domain.
For strict function space, happens to be a retraction of . Just map all the to the function which does the exact same thing but also maps to . This is Scott-continuous, and the corresponding Scott-continuous section is just the obvious injection. -BC domains are closed under function space, as we've shown. And, Proposition 4.1.3 says that BC-domains are closed under retracts, so we know that is at least a BC-domain. All that remains to check is that has a countable basis. This follows by Lemma 3.1.3, that the retraction of the countable basis for is a basis for .
For bilimit, Proposition 4.1.6 says that bilimits of BC-domains are BC-domains, and the countability of the basis for the bilimit is taken care of by Theorem 3.3.11.1. And we're done! As long as we manage to prove the three missing pieces.
Missing piece 1: Try to prove that if is an -BC domain, then is bounded-complete and has a countable basis.
Given any two points , one of three cases occurs. First, and could both be . Second, without loss of generality, , and . Third, . Clearly, in the first case, the pairwise supremum exists, it's just . And in the second case, the pairwise supremum is just . In the third case, if , and there's an upper bound in , then the same upper bound exists in , and so we can get a supremum of and in , and then it remains a supremum in . This establishes bounded-completeness.
As for a countable basis, is clearly countable. We'll show that it works as a basis. Given any ,
Now, approximates all , so this turns into
And then, we've got two possible cases. One is where . In this case, isn't in the original , and can't be in the original basis, so the supremum just turns into ie and we're done with that case. In the other possible case, , so is in the original . Obviously, this supremum is entirely of stuff below , so the supremum will be equal or less than . So our new proof target will be that
in order to show equality. So, let's begin. We have
Because is continuous. Since, for any , we have , we've shown that is a countable basis for . That's one part down.
Missing piece 2: Try to prove that if are -BC domains, then is bounded-complete and has a countable basis.
Given any two points , one of two cases occurs. First, and could both be in the same original domain, or they could be in different original domains. If there's an upper bound for and , they must be in the same original domain, and then we can appeal to bounded-completeness of or (whichever one the two points are in) in order to find a suprema for the two. this establishes bounded-completeness.
As for a countable basis, is clearly countable since the two sets we're unioning are countable. We'll show that it works as a basis. Given any , without loss of generality, we can assume that , because the same upcoming proof will work if . Then we have
Now, since by assumption, the only thing in which approximates is , so we have
And then, we've got two possible cases. One is where . In this case, the only thing in which approximates is itself, so we get
and we're done there. In the second case, . In this case, since must be in and approximate , we have
because is continuous and we're done. The same proof works for points in , so since we have , we've shown that is a countable basis for . That's the second part down.
Missing Piece 3: If are -BC domains, then has a countable basis.
This will rely on a proof very similar to a stage in our proof of Theorem 2. Our proposed basis for , given a countable basis for and , is all the atomic step functions where and , and all finite suprema of such which exist. The atomic step functions are, if , then , and otherwise . So our task is now to show that . Clearly we have one direction of the inequality, that matches or exceeds the supremum, since everything in there approximates and thus is less than . So we'll focus on the other direction, showing that . This is doable by showing said result for all . So, let be arbitrary in . We then have
This occurs because is continuous, so . Then, is a continuous function, so we can move the directed supremum out of the function. Then, is continuous, so . For the final step, because , we have , so .
Now, we'll assume something for now, and loop back to prove it later. We'll assume that if , then . Assuming this works out, then for any choice of and from those two directed sets, since , we have , so . Accordingly, we can go
The first inequality happens because every pair for the first two directed suprema corresponds to an atomic step function which approximates , but there may be other step functions which approximate . The second inequality happens because is composed of atomic step functions which approximate , but also some other stuff. Then we just reexpress things a bit. Assuming this works out, then since is arbitrary, it'd show the other inequality direction, that and so, we'd have a countable basis for , showing it's an -BC domain.
We do, however, need to show our key intermediate result that
First, assume . Then, in order to show that , we need to pick an arbitrary directed set of functions, , with a supremum above , and show that there's a function in that collection which lies above . This is pretty easy, actually. Pick a suitable directed set . We have , so, we have
because of our starting assumption that , and being a directed collection of functions which matches or exceeds . Now, by the fact that approximates , and the directedness of the , there's an element of that which exceeds , which corresponds to some particular function . We have
Now, we just need to show and we'll have shown that for any directed set of functions with supremum above , it has a function which exceeds , and we'll be done. Let be arbitrary. We can split into two cases. One is , and one is . In the first case, we have
Because of how the atomic step function was defined, and we showed that already, and also since , we have and Scott-continuous functions (like ) are monotone. For the second case, we have
And we're done, we hit all our proof targets, the theorem follows now.
0 comments
Comments sorted by top scores.