On the ontological development of consciousness
post by jessicata (jessica.liu.taylor) · 2020-01-25T05:56:43.244Z · LW · GW · 7 commentsThis is a link post for https://unstableontology.com/2020/01/25/on-the-ontological-development-of-consciousness/
Contents
World-perception ontology Pattern-only ontology World-perception ontology results from stabilization Consciousness in world-perception ontology None 7 comments
This post is about what consciousness is, ontologically, and how ontologies that include consciousness develop.
The topic of consciousness is quite popular, and confusing, in philosophy. While I do not seek to fully resolve the philosophy of consciousness, I hope to offer an angle on the question I have not seen before. This angle is that of developmental ontology: how are "later" ontologies developed from "earlier" ontologies? I wrote on developmental ontology in a previous post, and this post can be thought of as an elaboration, which can be read on its own, and specifically tackles the problem of consciousness.
Much of the discussion of stabilization is heavily inspired by On the Origin of Objects, an excellent book on reference and ontology, to which I owe much of my ontological development. To the extent that I have made any philosophical innovation, it is in combining this book's concepts with the minimum-description-length principle, and analytic philosophy of mind.
World-perception ontology
I'm going to write a sequence of statements, which each make sense in terms of an intuitive world-perception ontology.
- There's a real world outside of my head.
- I exist and am intimately connected with, if not identical with, some body in this world.
- I only see some of the world. What I can see is like what a camera placed at the point my eyes are can see.
- The world contains objects. These objects have properties like shape, color, etc.
- When I walk, it is me who moves, not everything around me. Most objects are not moving most of the time, even if they look like they're moving in my visual field.
- Objects, including my body, change and develop over time. Changes proceed, for the most part, in a continuous way, so e.g. object shapes and sizes rarely change, and teleportation doesn't happen.
These all seem common-sensical; it would be strange to doubt them. However, achieving the ontology by which such statements are common-sensical is nontrivial. There are many moving parts here, which must be working in their places before the world seems as sensible as it is.
Let's look at the "it is me who moves, not everything around me" point, because it's critical. If you try shaking your head right now, you will notice that your visual field changes rapidly. An object (such as a computer screen) in your vision is going to move side-to-side (or top-to-bottom), from one side of your visual field to another.
However, despite this, there is an intuitive sense of the object not moving. So, there is a stabilization process involved. Image stabilization (example here) is an excellent analogy for this process (indeed, the brain could be said to engage in image stabilization in a literal sense).
The world-perception ontology is, much of the time, geocentric, rather than egocentric or heliocentric. If you walk, it usually seems like the ground is still and you are moving, rather than the ground moving while you're still (egocentrism), or both you and the ground moving very quickly (heliocentrism). There are other cases such as vehicle interiors where what is stabilized is not the Earth, but the vehicle itself; and, "tearing" between this reference frame and the geocentric reference frame can cause motion sickness.
Notably, world-perception ontology must contain both (a) a material world and (b) "my perceptions of it". Hence, the intuitive ontological split between material and consciousness. To take such a split to be metaphysically basic is to be a Descartes-like dualist. And the split is ontologically compelling enough that such a metaphysics can be tempting.
Pattern-only ontology
William James famously described the baby's sense of the world as a "blooming, buzzing confusion". The image presented is one of dynamism and instability, very different from world-perception ontology.
The baby's ontology is closer to raw percepts than an adult's is; it's less developed, fewer things are stabilized, and so on. Babies generally haven't learned object permanence; this is a stabilization that is only developed later.
The most basic ontology consists of raw percepts (which cannot even be considered "percepts" from within this ontology), not even including shapes; these percepts may be analogous to pixel-maps in the case of vision, or spectrograms in the case of hearing, but I am unsure of these low-level details, and the rest of this post would still apply if the basic percepts were e.g. lines in vision. Shapes (which are higher-level percepts) must be recognized in the sea of percepts, in a kind of unsupervised learning.
The process of stabilization is intimately related to a process of pattern-detection. If you can detect patterns of shapes across time, you may reify such patterns as an object. (For example, a blue circle that is present in the visual field, and retains the same shape even as it moves around the field, or exits and re-enters, may be reified as a circular object). Such pattern-reification is analogous to folding a symmetric image in half: it allows the full image to be described using less information than was contained in the original image.
In general, the minimum description length principle says it is epistemically correct to posit fewer objects to explain many. And, positing a small number of shapes to explain many basic percepts, or a small number of objects to explain a large number of shapes, are examples of this.
From having read some texts on meditation (especially Mastering the Core Teachings of the Buddha), and having meditated myself, I believe that meditation can result in getting more in-touch with pattern-only ontology, and that this is an intended result, as the pattern-only ontology necessarily contains two of the three characteristics (specifically, impermanence and no-self).
To summarize: babies start from a confusing point, where there are low-level percepts, and patterns progressively recognized in them, which develops ontology including shapes and objects.
World-perception ontology results from stabilization
The thesis of this post may now be stated: world-perception ontology results from stabilizing a previous ontology that is itself closer to pattern-only ontology.
One of the most famous examples of stabilization in science is the movement from geocentrism to heliocentrism. Such stabilization explains many epicycles in terms of few cycles, by changing where the center is.
The move from egocentrism to geocentrism is quite analogous. An egocentric reference frame will contain many "epicycles", which can be explained using fewer "cycles" in geocentrism.
These cycles are literal in the case of a person spinning around in a circle. In a pattern-only ontology (which is, necessarily, egocentric, for the same reason it doesn't have a concept of self), that person will see around them shapes moving rapidly in the same direction. There are many motions to explain here. In a world-percept ontology, most objects around are not moving rapidly; rather, it is believed that the self is spinning.
So, the egocentric-to-geocentric shift is compelling for the same reason the geocentric-to-heliocentric shift is. It allows one to posit that there are few motions, instead of many motions. This makes percepts easier to explain.
Consciousness in world-perception ontology
The upshot of what has been said so far is: the world-perception ontology results from Occamian symmetry-detection and stabilization starting from a pattern-only ontology (or, some intermediate ontology).
And, the world-perception ontology has conscious experience as a component. For, how else can what were originally perceptual patterns be explained, except by positing that there is a camera-like entity in the world (attached to some physical body) that generates such percepts?
The idea that consciousness doesn't exist (which is asserted by some forms of eliminative materialism) doesn't sit well with this picture. The ontological development that produced the idea of the material world, also produced the idea of consciousness, as a dual. And both parts are necessary to make sense of percepts. So, consciousness-eliminativism will continue to be unintuitive (and for good epistemic reasons!) until it can replace world-perception ontology with one that achieves percept-explanation that is at least as effective. And that looks to be difficult or impossible.
To conclude: the ontology that allows one to conceptualize the material world as existing and not shifting constantly, includes as part of it conscious perception, and could not function without including it. Without such a component, there would be no way to refactor rapidly shifting perceptual patterns into a stable outer world and a moving point-of-view contained in it.
7 comments
Comments sorted by top scores.
comment by Charlie Steiner · 2020-01-27T03:03:49.183Z · LW(p) · GW(p)
This is a really nice way of explaining the "camera-like point of view." Obv. "consciousness" has a bunch of extra grab-bag components that we associate with the word.
comment by ImmortalRationalist · 2020-01-27T03:00:42.816Z · LW(p) · GW(p)
What do you think of Avshalom Elitzur's arguments for why he reluctantly thinks interactionist dualism is the correct metaphysical theory of consciousness?
Replies from: jessica.liu.taylor↑ comment by jessicata (jessica.liu.taylor) · 2020-01-27T06:38:14.759Z · LW(p) · GW(p)
Responding to a few points from his article:
Moreover, once you assume that the brain operates in compliance with physical law, qualia must not play any role in the brain’s operation.
Not true if "qualia" refers to a high-level property of some matter.
Next consider a plant that has not been watered for several days, nearly dying. You water it, and soon its leaves stretch again and regain their vitality. Should you invoke the qualia of “thirst” or “slaking thirst” to explain what happened?
These explanations aren't actually completely stupid; if the plant is optimizing then its optimization could possibly neatly be described by analogy with properties of human optimization that are perceivable in qualia. Maybe empathizing with a plant is a good way of understanding its optimization. Of course, the analogy isn't great (though is much better in the case of large animals), hence why I'm saying the explanations are "not completely stupid" rather than "good".
Well, if a non-physical cause plays a role in any process, than some of physics’ most revered laws, such as energy and momentum conservation, are violated.
False dichotomy, the explanations may apply to different properties of the process, or to different levels of analysis of the process. (I am, here, rejecting the principle of unique causality)
Software, just like hardware, is a physical configuration of matter.
"Is" seems like overeager reductionism. Telling what program a given computer is running, based on its physical configuration, is nontrivial.
Identity/double-aspect theory: The quale and the percept are one and the same process, only perceived as different.
This seems true. Note that "perceived as different" is doing a lot of work here. Qualia are known "directly" in a way that is close to metaphysically basic, whereas percepts are known indirectly, e.g. by looking at a brain scan of one's self or another person (note, this observation is also known through qualia, indirectly, since the brain scan must be observed). These are different epistemic modalities, that could nonetheless always yield the same information due to being two views on the same process.
This can be succinctly put as the Qualia Inaction Postulate: Any behavior would be exactly the same have there been no qualia.
False under identity/double-aspect theory. Because changing qualia means changing percepts too.
The fact that humans are baffled by the Percepts-Qualia Nonidentity, and express this bafflement by their observable behavior, is a case where qualia per se – as nonidentical with percepts – play a causal role in a physical process.
"Percept" as he uses the term refers to the entire brain processing starting from seeing something, including the part of the processing that processes things through world-perception ontology, self-concepts, etc. So "qualia per se - as nonidentical with percepts" is already assuming the falsity of identity/double-aspect theory.
Notice, first, that by this explanation-away the physicalist position commits itself, for the first time, to a falsifiable prediction: When future neurophysiology becomes advanced enough to point out the neural correlates of false beliefs, a specific correlate of this kind would be found to underlie the bafflement about qualia
Why would there be "neural correlates of false beliefs"? The brain can't tell that all of its false beliefs are false; that would require omniscience.
If a proof is ever given that an intelligent system, by virtue of physical laws alone, must state that it has qualia which are nonidentical with percepts, then the age-old Mind-Body Problem would finally get a definite solution – a physicalist one. The Percept-Qualia Nonidentity would turn out to be nothing but an unfortunate misperception, inherent to all intelligent systems, and the problem would turn out to be a pseudo-problem.
I believe my post gives something close to such a proof (not complete, but suggestive).
Chalmers has struggled with a similar idea in his discussion of “zombies.” These creatures are very instructive. Imagine intelligent beings that resemble us in every detail of our physiology, neuroanatomy and chemistry, but have no qualia. This, recall, is perfectly consistent with physics – in fact, as noted above, zombies accord with physics more than the existence of non-zombies.
Zombies may be ruled out philosophically/metaphysically/etc without being ruled out by physics. So assuming zombies are possible is already baking in assumptions.
Notice that in this case we can determine with certainty the cause of this bafflement. Since Charmless is man-made, we can rule out the possibility that his bafflement is the result of some pre-installed “bug” such as an explicit command to express bafflement or some deliberate misperception imposed on it. In other words, we can rule out any cause to Charmless’ assertion about having qualia other than his really having them.
Being susceptible to optical illusions doesn't have to be explicitly programmed in. This is assuming all misperceptions are deliberate which is false (it assumes a kind of omniscence).
Next ask Charmless: Can you conceive of a duplicate of you (henceforth Harmless) who is identical to you but lacks Q? His answer, by (3), must be “No; unmediated percepts must occur by physical law.”
I don't see at all how this follows.
.......
In summary: the article seems like a confused mess, making both technical errors and questionable metaphysical assumptions, such that it neither rules out percept-qualia identity nor epiphenomenalism.
comment by ToadMan11 · 2020-12-08T19:48:46.409Z · LW(p) · GW(p)
how else can what were originally perceptual patterns be explained, except by positing that there is a camera-like entity in the world (attached to some physical body) that generates such percepts?
This sentence makes a big leap. Here, you've vaguely defined consciousness as a camera-like entity that generates such percepts; the percepts in question being, apparently, just those percepts that are too difficult, complex, or high-level to explain in the manner that you were able to explain shapes as percepts derived from pixel maps.
That's why it's a leap in my opinion; you build up from raw percepts to pattern recognition, and from there, to an unspecified level of understanding the world somewhere between that of a baby and that of an adult, using stabilization as the vehicle and providing good examples, analogies, and explanations. But from there, you leap from recognizing shapes to world-perception ontology in one fell swoop, using consciousness as the catch-all. You offer a vague notion of what consciousness does, but no explanation of how it accomplishes it. What are the inputs and outputs of consciousness, and why must it be consciousness that produces those outputs rather than some part of the brain? Or if consciousness is that part of the brain, why is it a camera-like entity attached to the body rather than just circuitry in the body itself?
You go on to offer somewhat of a passing criticism of eliminative materialism, but because of the gaps above, it's not a valid criticism as far as I can tell. I say that because, in addition to the gaps above, the biggest arguments against your thesis ("the ontology...includes...conscious perception") come from physics, physics being at the core of any materialism. So before those arguments can be made, I needed to re-credit eliminative materialism.
When you conclude that consciousness is attached to some physical body, and that consciousness even plays a role in that body's understanding of and functioning within the world, you cannot escape physics. The body's actions within the world are coupled with the body's "understanding" of the world. The electrical signals generated by the brain, sent into the muscles, resulting in accelerations of body parts, are coupled with and motivated by the body's "understanding." Somewhere within that leap you made, there needs to be some explanation of how the consciousness could cause physical phenomena without breaking any laws of physics. That, it seems to me, is much more likely to be impossible than the ability of consciousness-eliminativism to explain these percepts in question.
And both parts are necessary to make sense of percepts.
Why? What does the consciousness part even do, exactly?
the ontology that allows one to conceptualize the material world as existing and not shifting constantly, includes as part of it conscious perception, and could not function without including it
What does the consciousness add to the perception? What does consciousness do that the circuitry of the brain could not possibly do?
Without such a component, there would be no way to refactor rapidly shifting perceptual patterns into a stable outer world and a moving point-of-view contained in it.
Why not?
comment by TAG · 2020-01-27T16:18:35.469Z · LW(p) · GW(p)
And, the world-perception ontology has conscious experience as a component. For, how else can what were originally perceptual patterns be explained, except by positing that there is a camera-like entity in the world (attached to some physical body) that generates such percepts?
-
You are implicitly explaining only one aspect or definition of consciousness: the existence of a subjective point of view. Other aspects such as high order thought or qualua are not dealt with.
-
Although you use the term "ontology" you are not attempting to explain what is ultimately real... both pattern ontology and object ontology as you describe them are phenomenological, from the perspective of the subject. A realist could still object that consciousness hasn't been shown to feature in the basic ontology.
↑ comment by jessicata (jessica.liu.taylor) · 2020-01-27T20:16:44.356Z · LW(p) · GW(p)
-
Agree regarding high order thought, but "qualia" seems to mean the contents of the subjective point of view? Based on SEP article. "There is something it is like for me to undergo each state, some phenomenology that it has. Philosophers often use the term ‘qualia’ (singular ‘quale’) to refer to the introspectively accessible, phenomenal aspects of our mental lives."
-
I agree with this. I do think a materialist should be sympathetic to naturalized epistemology which includes developmental psychology as a source of information on what a human could possibly workably consider to be real (and, what they "actually consider to be real" in a psychological sense).
↑ comment by TAG · 2020-03-15T14:20:11.533Z · LW(p) · GW(p)
Agree regarding high order thought, but “qualia” seems to mean the contents of the subjective point of view? Based on SEP article. “There is something it is like for me to undergo each state, some phenomenology that it has. Philosophers often use the term ‘qualia’ (singular ‘quale’) to refer to the introspectively accessible, phenomenal aspects of our mental lives.”
I don't see if that is agreeing with my point or not.