Meaningful things are those the universe possesses a semantics for

post by Abhimanyu Pallavi Sudhir (abhimanyu-pallavi-sudhir) · 2022-12-12T16:03:31.413Z · LW · GW · 14 comments

Contents

  Contents
  Motivation and a cringey rant [skip for the technical meat]
  Gödel's first incompleteness theorem
  Gödel's second incompleteness theorem
  Semantics and truth
  Exercises
  Reflection and ordinals
  Chaitin and complexity
  Empiricism and the Löbstacle
  General reading
None
14 comments

Logic courses are very risk-averse to talking about philosophy. This is bad, because philosophy is the motivation/intuition for logic & TCS. This essay gives a scout's view.

Epistemic status: A computer scientist would nod through Chapters 2-5, at least after first looking at the logician for approval. Subsequent chapters take a philosophical stance, namely that expressed in the title.


Contents

  1. Motivation and a cringey rant [skip for the technical meat]
  2. Gödel's first incompleteness theorem
  3. Gödel's second incompleteness theorem
  4. Semantics and truth
  5. Exercises
  6. Reflection and ordinals
  7. Chaitin and complexity
  8. Empiricism and the Löbstacle

[A rough version of Chs 1-5 post initially appeared as a math stackexchange answer and on my blog; I wrote it as I learned, and am posting more refined writing here.]


Motivation and a cringey rant [skip for the technical meat]

There are several immediate philosophical questions a beginner may ask when first hearing of Gödel's incompleteness theorem, such as: 

  1. Does Gödel's theorem apply to humans? If so, how are we able to tell that the Gödel sentence is true, or that some program doesn't halt?
  2. Does Gödel's theorem imply that there are questions about the universe, or about mathematics, whose answers we can never learn? Are these questions at least comprehensible to us?
  3. What's with the suggestive analogy between logic and computation, and how can we make it more precise? If Gödel applies to humans, are we formal systems or programs?
  4. If "true" is different from "provable", what does "true" even mean?
  5. How do we know that (e.g.) ZFC is consistent? We keep talking about the "true" model, how do we even identify this true model? 

Unlike other areas of science that lay-people find weird and philosophers say absurd things about (such as relativity and quantum mechanics), these questions are honestly legitimate and relevant for AI work (the only such question that isn't legitimate is "Does Gödel preclude a TOE?"). 

Some very wrong ways to answer these questions/to introduce mathematical logic:

  1. Gödel's theorem applies to specific types of formal systems, and says nothing about human reasoning. It just means we can't apply an algorithm to answer every question, not that we can't do so by other, more creative means! [Dude, do something non-algorithmic and show me.]
  2. Gödel's theorem is no biggie! It's just like how commutativity is independent of the axioms of group theory! [I literally can't predict if "Halt if Abhimanyu thinks I don't halt" halts, and you think this is like commutativity??]
  3. It's ok, you just need a stronger set of axioms. [But how do I know which axioms to use? You can't just say "observe the real world and figure it out"; we believe in arbitrary strengthenings of ZFC without doing any observations for it, so there must be some theoretical reasoning.]

It's a terrible habit, motivated by an averseness to risk and effort, of just giving the minimal technically-correct answer that still allows you to cover your ass and feign wisdom when someone rights their wrong question [LW · GW], by pompously sneering "that's a completely different question!" [You knew what my question was! You could have made it more precise too!]

It's like how religious people deal with "questions we cannot answer" by making up "answers we may not question"; now religious people no longer exist, so instead we have Redditors, who've found yet another way to deal with it: "deny that the question exists". 

You may go your entire life dismissing the questions that enter your mind as being imprecise, even though there are ways to tell that there is something of non-trivial value there, never saying anything that doesn't offer the security of already having been said in a textbook to protect you ...

... but hey, this way at least no one will call you a crank for entertaining weird questions.

[There are kids out there starving for an interesting problem to work on [? · GW], and you're going to deny and strawman the ones you get?!!]

[This is how frequentist statistics survived for so long, by the way. Yes, it is technically true that "5% is the probability of the data given the null hypothesis, not the converse", but also completely useless to pretend that that's where the reasoning ends, because at the end of the day you need to act based on these probabilities, and for that you need the probability of the null hypothesis being true, no matter how "arbitrary" it is to calculate this. The Bayesian is the man in the arena, while you're just in the audience going "I can't talk about being the man in the arena, I can only talk about what I'd do if I were the man in the arena ... "]


Gödel's first incompleteness theorem

Here's a general version of Gödel's first incompleteness theorem:

Let Bob be a computer programmed to read Alice's mind, and do something different from what Alice expects him to do.

Then Alice cannot predict Bob's actions. She must either have no opinion of it (incomplete) or have a wrong opinion of it (-unsound).

That's it. It's just a particularly adversarial measurement problem. There's only two assumptions that this requires:

  1. Alice can conceptualize computers.
  2. Bob is able to read Alice's mind.

If Alice is a formal system (where the latter reads as "Alice's theorems are computably enumerable"), this is the classic theorem.

If Alice is just some arbitrary algorithm, then this is the Halting problem.

You can play the part of Alice and write Bob as a program on your computer.

Gödel's argument (and also e.g. Quine's paradox) works by introducing self-reference through logical correlation. You can't even have beliefs on "the rest of the world", because the rest of the world can contain models of you.


Gödel's second incompleteness theorem

Realistically, if Alice were an enumerator for a formal system, and Bob was a program "halt iff Alice proves I don't halt", then Bob would never halt, and Alice would be unable to prove this fact. But surely if this were us running the enumerator, we would realize this ("Clearly the only possibility is that Bob doesn't halt but I don't prove this"). Is this a limitation of formal systems?

Of course not; we can formalize this reflective reasoning too: 

And you realize the implicit assumption made in this reasoning, that if Alice proves something, it is true [i.e. Alice is sound]. Alice is not allowed to believe this. This is Gödel's second theorem. 

Notice how we are only allowed to deduce that Bob never halts when Bob depends on the beliefs of the proof enumerator/Alice only, NOT when Bob depends on our more reflective belief. We are allowed to believe in the soundness of this proof enumerator/Alice, we are not allowed to believe in the soundness of our "entire" belief.


Semantics and truth

Does a person (or computer) really "compute", do they really have "beliefs" and "preferences", or are they just a physical process?

Any work with agents/computer science necessarily involves a layer of "interpretation" to assign meaning to their actions, or to decide that their beliefs are "true". 

A language captures an agent's imagination; a theory captures an agent's beliefs. 

In formal logic, a language is a set of strings ("sentences") and a theory is a subset of those strings ("theorems"). 

Often-time, the theory is specified as the set of consequences (following some rules called a "logic") of some "axioms". We like this set to be computably enumerable.

Bob can simulate Alice if he can imagine things like "Alice believes X". This only requires his imagination (language) to be expressive enough. He needn't know everything that Alice believes, just be able to imagine that she does. 

Bob can model Alice if he can translate her imagination into his by a computable function (for FOL theories this translation function is the T-schema) and believes the things she believes. This requires his beliefs (theory) to be strong enough. 

Hopefully this puts the question "What's stronger, logic or computation?" completely to rest. A theory may be expressive enough to simulate any program, that doesn't make it strong -- even PA simulates ZFC. But for any meaningful theory, there's a program that models it. 

A simulation is a superficial understanding. You can simulate topology by learning the axioms and applying them randomly, with no understanding of why it's useful.

A model is a deep understanding. If you have a mental model of topology, i.e. if you have things that its theorems apply to and are convinced that they apply to them, you can apply the heuristics you already have for these things to develop the theory.

There is a particular perspective in logic where you fix a base theory (a "foundation for mathematics") and consider all other theories in its semantics, i.e. as modelled by it. This is called model theory, and it makes perfect sense to study logic this way, because that's how we study all other mathematics! But that's not useful for philosophy.

If Bob models Alice, he judges a thing imagined by her to be "True" if he believes it (or rather his translation of it). This is the definition of truth according to "Convention T"/"the semantic theory of truth". There are other definitions of truth, but interpretation is fundamental to all of them.

Now that we have defined truth, we can formulate the Liar paradox.

[We can think of sentences and theorems as "questions" and "answers" respectively. A valid sentence of Alice is a question she might ask, a true theorem of Bob is an answer he may give.]

For any sentence P, suppose Alice can ask "Is P true?" such that Bob will answer YES iff he believes P [this is the definition of truth, per Convention T].

But then what if P is the liar sentence -- or in terms of Convention T, "Bob will answer YES to the opposite of this sentence"?

This leads to "Tarski's theorem": Alice can't even ask "Is P true?", can't even formulate a general notion of truth (of Bob believing his interpretation of her statement), because when truth is relative in this sense, formulating truth would lead to a tower of increasing complexity: "Is P true?" really asks "Would Bob answer YES if I asked him P?", but Bob then needs to interpret this sentence [answer this question], ad infinitum.


Exercises

  1. Turing degrees
    1. Prove the unsolvability of the Entscheidungsproblem [that there is no algorithm that determines if ZFC proves a given statement].
    2. Your immediate reaction should be one of puzzlement, that ZFC apparently "knows more" than any algorithm does, apparently breaking what earlier seemed to be a symmetry between logic and computation. Resolve this confusion. [You should arrive at the notion of "Turing equivalence". I would also formulate the precise correspondence between logic and computation as: Theories (at least the ones that we care about, i.e. can realistically capture an agent's beliefs) are programs, namely their theorem enumerators. But also theories are capable of proving things about programs, just as they are capable of proving things about stronger theories; they just don't believe those things themselves.]
    3. List examples of things that are Turing equivalent. 
    4. A Turing equivalence class is called a Turing degree. In particular, we denote the class of computable sets by  (the smallest Turing degree), and denote the class of successive Halting Oracles by 
  2. Arithmetical hierarchy
    1. There is a fundamental relationship between  statements and computable enumerability. State this precisely. [You should arrive at the definition of a "-decidable problem".]
    2. What about  statements?
    3. What about  statements?
    4. What about  statements?
    5. You should now be able to motivate the "Arithmetical hierarchy" -- the hierarchy of FOL sentences (equivalently FOL-definable sets): a  sentence is one that starts with some exists then alternates  times between consecutive sequences of foralls and exists; a  sentence is one that starts with some foralls then alternates  times between consecutive sequences of exists and foralls. 
    6. Prove Post's theorem: that  is precisely the set of problems that are computably enumerable by a Turing machine with access to an Oracle for .
  3. Miscellaneous paradoxes
    1. Gödel's second theorem and Tarski's theorem are both ways of suggesting that "you can't have a belief about your truest beliefs". A third way, Löb's theorem, says: if , then . I.e. the only things you can believe in your soundness for are the things you believe anyway. Prove this theorem using Curry's paradox ("If this sentence is true, then Germany borders China.") as a hint. Phrase this in terms of a computer program.
    2. Suppose instead of Contrarian Bob, we have Conformist Carl, who reads Alice's mind and halts iff she believes he will. Will Carl halt? [It's shocking that Löb's theorem has such a thing as an application.]
    3. But isn't Carl's situation symmetric? If instead Carl were to just follow "do whatever Alice believes he will", what would happen? [Formulate this situation very carefully logically.]
    4. Formally write down Berry's paradox and figure out what goes wrong there.
    5. Formally write down the jailor paradox and figure out what goes wrong there. [Answer: such a jailor actually cannot exist, but you need to argue this carefully.]

... the trend of how many results are treated: first they are considered major results, then interesting results, then they become exercises in yellow books.

(a comment by a certain Joshua Zelinsky on Shtetl-Optimized)


Reflection and ordinals

Eliezer has suggested [LW · GW] that Gödel's second theorem can be intuitively understood as a statement of humility: "you can't believe something just because you believe it" (perhaps suggesting that we should therefore find the theorem unsurprising as a result). I'm not sure that this is a correct explanation; the word "because" is rather trippy here, and you also can't believe that you're right 80% of the time or 20% or something (or have a calibration map). I think it is a fake explanation [LW · GW]; it's like saying neural networks are to be expected because they look like brains or because the world is hierarchical or something. It's an attempt to make Gödel intuitive, rather than make your intuition model Gödel [LW · GW]. Similar analogies to education systems trying to "make math fun", when they should be training the children to naturally be excited about math.

The correct understanding of Gödel's second theorem -- as well as Tarski's theorem, and Löb's theorem -- I think, is that you are not allowed to have beliefs about your beliefs. Or rather: you are not allowed to have beliefs about your truest, most final beliefs. 

Because your beliefs just can't be big enough to contain themselves. Even in the most basic setting -- if you have a universe that is in one of two states, a sample space of  but then you add an agent that believes one of those states to be true, your sample space of the universe including that agent needs to be . If you want the agent's beliefs to be complete for this sample space, you then go up to , etc. 

But at no point can you ask the agent's beliefs to be fully complete -- to be complete for itself. There's just not enough space, and just as the traditional Cantor diagonalization is a proof of "not enough space" for cardinalities, the diagonalization arguments found in Gödel proofs are natural generalizations of this idea.

Don't get me wrong -- you can certainly have beliefs like "I believe that I believe there is a dragon", etc. It's just that this will always be at a higher "level" than the earlier set of beliefs, so that earlier set of beliefs doesn't express the set of all your beliefs, so you can never quite quantify over all your beliefs, at all levels. The reason why it's OK for us to "informally believe but not prove that Bob never halts" has nothing to do with that belief being informal, it is because the formal system no longer represents our true belief, and Bob is only trying to fuck with our formal system, not our true belief. But Bob can always fuck with our true beliefs if he wants.

How far can we actually reflect on our beliefs? You may think one can have beliefs about beliefs, beliefs about beliefs about beliefs, etc. -- for any integer. This is equivalent to thinking "At t = 0, I think Bob will halt; at t = 1, I realize this belief of mine means that Bob will not halt; at t =3, I reflect on that and realize that Bob will halt, ... " But are not constrained to be so stupid, we can also predict all our future such reflections and immediately, in finite time, form a belief about all the reflections that we would have done if we had been so simplistic. We could call this reflection , and we can accomplish it in t = 1, then at t = 2 we reflect on that ...

In general, we can reflect up to any ordinal. For the  toy model described earlier, the idea is that the set of beliefs at stage  would be  (aka ), i.e. agent 's belief is a function that takes in a natural number  and gives agent 's belief [which is itself a vector of size ] ... but there's a caveat! Not every function/binary sequence can realistically represent the beliefs of a computable agent, only the computable ones can. The beliefs of each agent is a program. 

[Let that sink in.]

Here are some general constructions for agents that reflect up to particular ordinals ( is some pre-specified computable function that defines how the agent reflects).

  agent(n) = function():
  	initialize B
  	n times:
    	B = f(B)
agent(omega) = function(i):
  	initialize B
  	i times:
    	B = f(B)
agent(omega + n) = function():
  	agent(omega) = function(i):
  	    initialize B
  	    i times:
  	        B = f(B)
  	 n times:
  	     B = f(B) 
agent(omega * 2) = function(i):
  	agent(omega) = function(j):
  	    initialize B
  	    j times:
  	        B = f(B)
  	 i times:
  	     B = f(B) 
agent(omega * n) = function(i):
     initialize alpha(omega * 0) as before
  	 B[0] = alpha(omega * (n - 1))
  	 i times: B = f(B)
agent(omega ^ 2) = function(i):
  	 initialize alpha(omega * n) as before
  	 return alpha(omega * i)

OK I've written these programs in ridiculous short-hand -- in reality the program for agent  is a function that takes as input any ordinal  and give as output the program for agent 

But for a general ordinal, this function may not be computable! In particular, since any computable ordinals may be inputted as the code for the program that decides the corresponding order, this means that the belief "program" for  can take any program as input, discover what order it computes, and output that program's belief program. This is a violation of Rice's theorem, which says that there is no algorithm that can determine what any algorithm does [obviously!], so "agent " isn't a computable program. 

You can only reflect up to computable ordinals. The Church-Kleene Ordinal places a hard cap on reflection; you can get arbitrarily close to it (i.e. exceed every computable ordinal), but never reach it.

This wisdom transfers over to strengthening a theory by reflecting on it. There is a program that enumerates  (the -th reflection of ) for all computable ordinals , but no more. The minimal length of this program (Kolmogorov complexity) is non-decreasing in , and approaches  as .


Chaitin and complexity

REALITY CHECK: you cannot reflect up to any arbitrary computable ordinal [a program that can reflect up to any arbitrary computable ordinal has complexity , i.e. not a program]. Or rather: you cannot reflect up to any arbitrary computable ordinal -- you are some program, and you are bounded by whatever your computational power is.

Things are not so hopeless. You can build a computer that is better than you -- so in the end, you are only limited by the computational power of the universe/of physics.

But don't we understand, intuitively, transfinite induction up to arbitrary ordinals?

No -- because you are not capable of actually reasoning with these extremely strong theories, so such a "belief" has no meaning, much like you can't reason with an uncomputable theory. You can imagine such a theory, but you cannot believe it.

We can formalize these complexity-theoretic considerations:

The natural question to ask here: is the converse true?

Aside.

That's why we have logic

More precisely: that's why we have semantics.

The program a = [1, 0, 0, 0, 1, ... ]; return a[turing_number(input)] could decide halting for programs of length < n, but the only way to even claim that this is what the program does, to assign meaning to the program's actions, is through the eyes of another program which models (not just simulates) it.

At the end of the day, we want to know if we -- or rather, the universe -- can know that a program halts. Or in other words: 

The things that are meaningful are the things that the universe possess a semantics for.

So if you ever wondered "how do we find the right axioms?" or "what does logic really mean?" -- remember: the axiom of choice is just metaphysics.


Empiricism and the Löbstacle

The "Löbstacle" can generally be defined as the question, "What is the rational basis for reflection and self-improvement (building a better computer)?" Even if we give a rational basis for reflection up to our own complexity, how could we possibly give a rational basis for "trusting the universe's computations"? -- if the universe is more complex than us, how can we assign semantics to it?

I believe the answer is empiricism. There isn't a way to say this without sounding like a deranged hippie, but I'll try: if a small program has access to a larger program (can run it and use its outputs), then for all intents and purposes, the latter can be considered a part of it (just like Alice cannot predict the actions of Bob, because by being able to read her mind, he is actually being more complex than her).

It's like, if we were a formal system we would have an axiom: whatever is observed is valid -- and this gives us access to all the computations the universe has performed yet. 

This is far from a formalized solution to the Löbstacle, but I think it's the right idea.

And that's all I'll say.

[ETA: not all empiricism is this. Empiricism also addresses regular statistical uncertainty, i.e. uncertainty about syntax, not just algorithmic uncertainty, i.e. uncertainty about semantics.]


General reading

Things I read:

Might also be worth reading on (but I haven't covered, because I don't understand the importance of) proof-theoretic ordinals. I believe a standard source is Rathjen.

14 comments

Comments sorted by top scores.

comment by Shmi (shminux) · 2022-12-12T22:31:58.781Z · LW(p) · GW(p)

Does Gödel's theorem imply that there are questions about the universe, or about mathematics, whose answers we can never learn? Are these questions at least comprehensible to us?

Note that this seems like a category error: mathematics is not physics, and building models of the universe is independent of mathematical theorems about soundness and consistency. Physicists (and humans in general) constantly use a self-contradictory patchwork of abstractions to make sense of the world. Yes, really.

If you want to investigate whether "there are questions about the universe... whose answers we can never learn", then you need to focus on learning. Specifically, a model of the universe an embedded agent has is a lossy compression of the "reality", so the question to ask would be "what kind of possible worlds compatible with observations would limit the extent of useful lossy compression?" Here is an example: most lossy image/sound and data compression algorithms are based on Digital Cosine Transform. At some point as the required compression degree gets too high, say, because we want so many details to be compressed in the number of bits that fit into the human brain, the compression fidelity might become unacceptably low, hitting the limits of our understanding, even in principle. 

You sort of hint at this approach with your mention of empiricism, there is no need to worry about the Loeb obstacle at all.

Replies from: abhimanyu-pallavi-sudhir
comment by Abhimanyu Pallavi Sudhir (abhimanyu-pallavi-sudhir) · 2022-12-13T06:45:36.231Z · LW(p) · GW(p)

I agree, and one could think of this in terms of markets: a market cannot capture all information about the world, because it is part of the world.

But I disagree that this is fundamentally unrelated -- here too the issue is that it would need to represent states of the world corresponding to what belief it expresses. Ultimately mathematics is supposed to represent the real world.

Replies from: shminux
comment by Shmi (shminux) · 2022-12-13T07:10:33.286Z · LW(p) · GW(p)

Ultimately mathematics is supposed to represent the real world.

Well, I think a better way to put it is that mathematics is sometimes a part of some models of the world. The relationship is world -> inputs -> models <-> math. Whether the part of mathematics that deals with self-reference and soundness and completeness of formal systems corresponds to an accurate and useful model of the world is not at all obvious. So, yeah, some parts of mathematics lossily represent some parts of the world. But it is a pretty weak statement.

Replies from: lahwran, abhimanyu-pallavi-sudhir
comment by the gears to ascension (lahwran) · 2022-12-13T07:48:50.599Z · LW(p) · GW(p)

Half-joking: Find me a mathematical statement that purports to not describe the real world and I'll show you a mathematical statement that describes patterns in constructions of symbols made of the real world. Territory comes first; math can show us perfect patterns in the territory, but by the same token, it can only ever be map. The map, being part of the territory, can then make insightful statements about itself, through many layers of patterns of patterns of patterns of patterns, but you've never seen a mathematical statement that wasn't in the territory.

Replies from: shminux, abhimanyu-pallavi-sudhir
comment by Shmi (shminux) · 2022-12-13T09:32:37.630Z · LW(p) · GW(p)

Of course math is in the territory, everything is. Embedded agency and all. But it does not mean that the particular part of the territory that is a specific part of math is also a lossy compression of a larger part of the territory.

comment by Abhimanyu Pallavi Sudhir (abhimanyu-pallavi-sudhir) · 2022-12-13T10:01:19.593Z · LW(p) · GW(p)

That's syntax, not semantics.

Replies from: lahwran
comment by the gears to ascension (lahwran) · 2022-12-13T17:43:18.922Z · LW(p) · GW(p)

HUH. iiiiinteresting...

comment by Abhimanyu Pallavi Sudhir (abhimanyu-pallavi-sudhir) · 2022-12-13T08:45:09.373Z · LW(p) · GW(p)

You overstate your case. The universe contains a finite amount of incompressible information, which is strictly less than the information contained in . That self-reference applies to the universe is obvious, because the universe contains computer programs.

The point is the universe is certainly a computer program, and that incompleteness applies to all computer programs (to all things with only finite incompressible information). In any case, I explained Godel  with an explicitly empirical example, so I'm not sure what your point is. 

Replies from: shminux
comment by Shmi (shminux) · 2022-12-13T09:24:52.596Z · LW(p) · GW(p)

That's about as much of an argument as saying that the universe is contained in the decimal expansion of Pi, therefore Pi has all the information one needs.

Replies from: abhimanyu-pallavi-sudhir
comment by Abhimanyu Pallavi Sudhir (abhimanyu-pallavi-sudhir) · 2022-12-13T10:00:44.639Z · LW(p) · GW(p)

It's really not, that's the point I made about semantics.

Eh that's kind-of right, my original comment there was dumb.

comment by mruwnik · 2022-12-13T16:13:46.884Z · LW(p) · GW(p)

So this is why you have to just assume that logic (or mathematics) works (as you can't prove it without using logic)!

Replies from: abhimanyu-pallavi-sudhir
comment by Abhimanyu Pallavi Sudhir (abhimanyu-pallavi-sudhir) · 2022-12-13T17:15:06.492Z · LW(p) · GW(p)

I don't think that's exactly true. But why do you think that follows from what I wrote?

Replies from: mruwnik
comment by mruwnik · 2022-12-13T17:34:23.433Z · LW(p) · GW(p)

I find that if I keep recursing deep enough, after a while I get to a point where I try to work out why I believe that I can believe that logic works. At which point I bounce off a wall, seeing as I'm trying to logically come up with a reason for it. 

Solipsism is similar - how do you know that you're not a brain in a vat? Or in general Descartes' demon. From my (admissively most likely confused) understanding, this would be another example of self reference, albeit in a roundabout way.

Replies from: abhimanyu-pallavi-sudhir
comment by Abhimanyu Pallavi Sudhir (abhimanyu-pallavi-sudhir) · 2022-12-13T18:06:25.144Z · LW(p) · GW(p)

I think that the philosophical questions you're describing actually evaporate and turn out to be meaningless once you think enough about them, because they have a very anthropic flavour.