Be Happier
post by Klevador · 2012-04-16T01:51:46.838Z · LW · GW · Legacy · 267 commentsContents
Money and Happiness Work Satisfaction Materialism and Purchasing Interpersonal Stretching Happiness (fighting hedonic adaptation) Appreciation Optimal Happification Some Key Terms Money and Happiness Spend on others, especially people you are close to. Don't be Stingy. Think about time, but don’t think of time in terms of money (“An hour of my time is worth…”). Being richer will not necessarily make you happier. Pitfall of being wealthy: your ability to savor positive emotions and experiences will be impaired. Don’t make money your priority. Financial aspirations are bad for family life (and the quality of interpersonal relationships is a strong predictor of happiness). Don’t live ‘high’. Avoid conspicuous consumption. More Recommendations WORK SATISFACTION Coping with Stress: React pragmatically rather than emotionally. Leaders and Entrepreneurs: Don’t take on too many business partners. (See also AUTONOMY below) Prefer the ‘approach’ path instead of the ‘avoid’ path. AUTONOMY: Make a point of prefering autonomous goals rather than heteronomous goals (goals imposed/expected by others). AUTONOMY: Make sure you have spare discretionary time — even at financial cost. Be passionate, but don’t obsess. “Passion Does Make a Difference to People’s Well-Being” (Philippe, Vallerand, & Lavigne, 2009) Do work that you enjoy doing. Flow. Set goals that are reasonably challenging and reasonably achievable. Prefer intrinsic (vs. extrinsic) goals MATERIALISM AND PURCHASING The Hedonic Treadmill: We adapt to life changes. Many things that give pleasure will soon cease to do so, thereby driving us to seek more, and more… Prefer experiential purchases; avoid materialistic goals. It is better to collect (positive) experiences than to collect things. Don’t engage in ‘comparison shopping.’ And don’t place much stock in the happiness potential of any one positive change. 'Follow the herd.' (Dunn et al., 2011) INTERPERSONAL Socialize — with the right people. Associate with happy people. Give the people around you opportunities to be generous. Ask them for favors. Be actively kind (and occasionaly reminisce about your recent acts of kindness). STRETCHING HAPPINESS (fighting hedonic adaptation) Choose smaller, more frequent successes rather than larger ones. Go for variety and surprise. Don’t keep doing the same thing. Savor the anticipation. Delay consumption. Actively anticipate good experiences. Divide positive experiences into smaller pleasures, if possible. Corollary: Conclude negative experiences as soon as possible. Make a point of avoiding experiences that make you feel bad. APPRECIATION Be grateful. Count your blessings (literally). Recycle happiness. Reminisce about good experiences. Think of counterfactuals. (“If I didn’t have this, what do I lose?”) Breathe deeply. Expand your time — by slowing down. Stay in the present. OPTIMAL HAPPIFICATION Actively want to be happier. Motivation and investment matter. Learn about the science of happiness. Internalize the recommendations in this article and in here. EXTRA CONSIDERATIONS It will be easier to stay happy when you become happier Happiness Interventions Work! Extra extra: Cultural Differences References None 267 comments
This started as an assignment to find out about the science of ‘buying happiness’ (using money to become happier) — hence the emphasis on money-and-happiness. I learned a great deal more than how to buy happiness, however, and the project became somewhat more generalized. It is not meant to be comprehensive, but perhaps it makes for a useful supplement to Luke’s How to be Happy. This post consists mostly of quoted material.
In A Nutshell
Money and Happiness
- Spend on others, especially people you are close to. Positive feedback loop: Prosocial spending makes you happier, and happiness makes you more likely to spend prosocially.
- Don’t be stingy. It's bad for your health.
- Don’t think too much about money. It will impair your savoring ability. It's also bad for your family life.
- Be time-aware, but don’t think of time in terms of money.
- Being richer will not necessarily make you happier.
- Do not live in wealthy enclaves.
- Avoid conspicuous consumption.
Work Satisfaction
- Coping with Stress: React pragmatically rather than emotionally.
- Go for ‘approach’ goals instead of ‘avoid’ goals.
- Autonomy: Make a point of prefering autonomous goals rather than heteronomous goals (goals imposed by others).
- Autonomy: Make sure you have spare discretionary time — even at financial cost.
- Be passionate, but don’t obsess.
- Do work that you enjoy doing. Flow.
- Set goals that are reasonably challenging and reasonably achievable.
Materialism and Purchasing
- Prefer experiential purchases; avoid materialistic goals.
- Keep your goals intrinsic.
- Don’t do ‘comparison shopping.’ And don’t place much stock in the happiness potential of any one positive change.
- Follow the herd. “The best way to predict how much we will enjoy an experience is to see how much someone else enjoyed it.”
Interpersonal
- Socialize with close others.
- Associate with happy people.
- Give the people around you opportunities to be generous. Ask them for favors.
- Be actively kind (and occasionaly reminisce about your recent acts of kindness).
Stretching Happiness (fighting hedonic adaptation)
- Go for smaller, more frequent successes rather than larger ones.
- Go for variety and surprise. Don’t keep doing the same thing.
- Savor anticipation. Delay consumption. Actively anticipate good experiences.
- Divide positive experiences into smaller pleasures, if possible.
- Corollary: Conclude negative experiences as soon as possible.
- Make a point of avoiding experiences that make you feel bad.
Appreciation
- Be grateful and count your blessings (literally). Recycle happiness by reminiscing about good experiences.
- Think of counterfactuals. (“If I didn’t have this positive thing, what do I lose?”)
- Breathe deeply. Expand your time — by slowing down.
- Stay in the present.
Optimal Happification
- Actively want to be happier. Motivation and investment matter.
- Learn about the science of happiness. Internalize the lessons in this article and in here.
Some Key Terms
- Subjective Well Being (SWB) aka happiness.
- Hedonic Adaptation — the phenomenon of (rapidly) diminishing positive or negative affect from any one experience or thing.
- Hedonic treadmill — the phenomenon of neverending aspirations for materialistic acquisitions that results from hedonic adaptation.
Money and Happiness
Spend on others, especially people you are close to.
Past research in our lab has repeatedly shown that people are happier when they use financial resources to benefit others rather than themselves [Aknin, Dunn, Sandstrom & Norton, submitted, 1,14].
... findings suggest that to reap the greatest emotional reward from spending on someone else, one should direct their purchases to close others
These findings should not be taken to suggest that people should avoid spending on weak social ties. Indeed, treating an acquaintance from yoga to a coffee after class might help to build a new strong tie. Thus, spending money on a weak social tie might help facilitate the development of new strong ties in the longer term.
… research on reciprocal altruism and the evolution of cooperation demonstrates that people ultimately benefit from behaving generously and cooperatively toward individuals with whom they are likely to interact in the future
The current results […] shed novel insight into translating spending choices into happiness: the next time you find a few spare dollars in your pocket, you will be happiest if you treat your best friend.
(Aknin, Sandstrom, Dunn, & Norton, 2011b)
This research also supports the broaden-and-build theory of positive emotions by demonstrating that higher levels of happiness may expand an individual’s mindset to include thoughts of others.
(Ahuvia, 2002)
... prosocial spending may be particularly promising route to prosocial behavior because it has been shown to increase happiness immediately after spending (Dunn et al. 2008, 2010) and later upon reflection, as demonstrated here.
... how money is spent may matter more than how much money is spent. That is, participants who recalled spending on others felt happier than those who spent money on themselves, and the benefits of prosocial spending were the same regardless of whether they spent $100 or just $20. Recent work suggests that prosocial behavior leads to emotional gains by providing opportunities for positive social contact (Aknin et al. 2011b); therefore, prosocial spending should promote happiness if the spending opportunity fosters positive relations with others, which may be largely independent of the specific amount of money spent. (Aknin, Dunn, & Norton, 2011a)
... participants assigned to spend a small windfall on someone else by purchasing a gift or making a donation to charity (prosocial spending) were significantly happier at the end of the day than participants assigned to spend the same size windfall by paying for a bill, expense, or gift for themselves (personal spending)
(Aknin, Dunn, & Norton, 2011a)
Positive feedback loop:
Taken together, our results show that
(a) recalling a past prosocial spending experience leads to higher levels of happiness,
(b) higher levels of happiness increase the likelihood of engaging in prosocial spending, and
(c) recalling a past experience of prosocial spending increases the likelihood of spending a new windfall on others to the extent that happiness levels are elevated in the interim. This suggests that spending money on others may be self-reinforcing as long as this prosocial experience provides happiness.
(Aknin, Dunn, & Norton, 2011a)
Being generous will make you happier.
experiments within two very different countries (Canada and Uganda) […] show that spending money on others has a consistent, causal impact on happiness.
In contrast to traditional economic thought—which places self-interest as the guiding principle of human motivation—our findings suggest that the reward experienced from helping others may be deeply ingrained in human nature, emerging in diverse cultural and economic contexts.
[In both] Canada and Uganda — [which] differ dramatically in national-level income and donation frequency, we find that individuals report significantly greater well-being after reflecting on a time when they spent money on others rather than themselves. This effect emerged consistently across these two cultures, even though the specific prosocial spending experiences participants described differed considerably. Thus, although prosocial spending differs in both frequency (Study 1) and form (Study 2) in poor versus wealthy countries, its emotional consequences are remarkably consistent.
(Aknin et al., 2010)
we found that spending more of one’s income on others predicted greater happiness both cross-sectionally (in a nationally representative survey study) and longitudinally (in a field study of windfall spending). Finally, participants who were randomly assigned to spend money on others experienced greater happiness than those assigned to spend money on themselves.
(Dunn, Aknin, & Norton, 2008)
...prosocial spending is consistently associated with greater happiness.
The robustness of this mechanism is supported by our finding that people seem to experience emotional benefits from sharing their financial resources with others not only in countries where such resources are plentiful, but also in impoverished countries where scarcity might seem to limit the possibilities to reap the gains from giving to others.
(Aknin et al., 2010)
Don't be Stingy.
Aside from the positive effect of generosity on your own happiness, stinginess makes you less healthy; it is easier to be happy when you are healthy.
The present research suggests that stingy economic behavior can produce a feeling of shame, which in turn drives secretion of the stress hormone cortisol.
... the present research provides support for Social Self-Preservation Theory, which posits that acute threats to the ‘social self’ induce shame and lead to increased cortisol, as part of a coordinated response to social threats (Dickerson, Gruenewald, & Kemeny, 2004a).
Our findings provide initial, suggestive evidence that shame and cortisol represent plausible emotional and biological pathways that might link everyday decisions about whether to help others with downstream consequences for one’s own health.
... stingy economic behavior predicts cortisol secretion only to the extent that stinginess provokes shame.
(Dunn et al., 2010)
Caveat: hedonic adaptation moderates the deleterious effect of bad health on well-being, but not entirely — and negative experiences are more powerful than positive experiences:
”To sum up almost two decades of research, bad is stronger than good.”
(Chancellor & Lyubomirsky, 2011)
(More on negative experiences farther down in ‘STRETCHING HAPPINESS’.)
Think about time, but don’t think of time in terms of money (“An hour of my time is worth…”).
... thinking about time in terms of money can influence how people experience pleasurable events by instigating greater impatience during unpaid time.
In three separate experiments we have demonstrated that bringing individuals’ effective hourly wage to their attention impairs the ability to derive happiness from pleasurable experiences.
One possible explanation is that impatience discourages savoring. Savoring is a form of emotional regulation which augments the happiness individuals derive from experiences (e.g. Bryant et al., 2005; Quoidbach, 2009; Tugade & Fredrickson, 2007).
... recent ethnographic research […] found that people who are paid by the hour narrowly evaluate their time use in terms of its economic returns. As a consequence, they tend to discount the worth of activities with non-economic benefits (Evans et al., 2004).
... the present findings suggest that thinking about time in terms of money is poised to affect our ability to smell the proverbial roses.
(DeVoe & House, 2012)
... there is a bi-directional relationship between the scarcity of time and its value: not only does having little time make it feel more valuable, but when time is more valuable, it is perceived as more scarce (DeVoe & Pfeffer, 2010).
(Aaker et al., 2010)
In an word priming experiment done in a cafe:
Pair-wise comparisons showed that individuals primed with time spent more of their time at the café socializing than those primed with money. Further, individuals primed with time spent less of their time working than those primed with money
Participants primed with money worked more than those in the control condition and participants primed with time worked less than those in the control condition
... participants primed with time were happier than those primed with money. […] Participants primed with time were also happier than those in the control condition [and] the happiness levels of those primed with money and those in the control condition did not differ significantly,
These results suggest that increasing the relative salience of time (vs. money) can increase happiness by leading people to behave in more connecting ways [and] can nudge someone to spend that extra hour at home rather than at the office, there finding greater happiness.
Focusing on money motivates one to work more, which is useful to know when struggling to put in that extra hour of work to meet a looming deadline. However, passing the hours working (although productive) does not translate into greater happiness. Spending time with loved ones does, and a shift in attention toward time proves an effective means to motivate this social connection.
... the relevant question may be not how much money people have, but rather how much attention people put on money.
Despite the belief that money is the resource most central to Americans’ pursuit of happiness, increased happiness requires a shift in attention toward time.
(Mogilner, 2010)
Being richer will not necessarily make you happier.
The belief that high income is associated with good mood is widespread but mostly illusory. People with above-average income are relatively satisfied with their lives but are barely happier than others in moment-to-moment experience, tend to be more tense, and do not spend more time in particularly enjoyable activities. Moreover, the effect of income on life satisfaction seems to be transient. We argue that people exaggerate the contribution of income to happiness because they focus, in part, on conventional achievements when evaluating their life or the lives of others.
The latter finding might help explain why income is more highly correlated with general life satisfaction than with experienced happiness, as tension and stress may accompany goal attainment, which in turn contributes to judgments of life satisfaction more than it does to experienced happiness.
Despite the weak relation between income and global life satisfaction or experienced happiness, many people are highly motivated to increase their income. In some cases, this focusing illusion may lead to a misallocation of time, from accepting lengthy commutes (which are among the worst moments of the day) to sacrificing time spent socializing (which are among the best moments of the day) (28, 29). An emphasis on the role of attention helps to explain both why many people seek high income—because their predictions exaggerate the increase in happiness due to the focusing illusion—and why the long- term effect of income gains become relatively small, because attention eventually shifts to less novel aspects of daily life.
(Kahneman, 2006)
It is found that higher income aspirations reduce people’s satisfaction with life. In Switzerland and the New German Laender, the negative effect of an increase in the aspiration level on well-being is of a similar absolute magnitude as the positive effect on well-being of an equal increase in income. This suggests that subjective well-being depends largely on the gap between income aspirations and actual income and not on the income level as such. the higher the ratio between aspired income and actual income, the less satisfied people are with their life, ceteris paribus. This supports the notion of a relative utility concept.
(Stutzer & Frey, 2010)
Emotional well-being also rises with log income, but there is no further progress beyond an annual income of ∼$75,000. Low income exacerbates the emotional pain associated with such misfortunes as divorce, ill health, and being alone.
[The data suggest that] above a certain level of stable income, individuals’ emotional well-being is constrained by other factors in their temperament and life circumstances.
(Kahneman & Deaton, 2010)
Pitfall of being wealthy: your ability to savor positive emotions and experiences will be impaired. Don’t make money your priority.
The present study provides the first evidence that money impairs people‘s ability to savor everyday positive emotions and experiences.
In a sample of working adults, wealthier individuals reported lower savoring ability.
... the negative impact of wealth on savoring undermined the positive effects of money on happiness.
... moving beyond self-report, participants exposed to a reminder of wealth spent less time savoring a piece of chocolate and exhibited reduced enjoyment of it. The present research supplies evidence for the previously untested notion that having access to the best things in life may actually undercut the ability to reap enjoyment from life‘s small pleasures.
In other words, one need not actually visit the pyramids of Egypt or spend a week in the legendary spas of Banff—simply knowing that these peak experiences are readily available may increase the tendency to take the small pleasures of daily life for granted.
... having access to the best things in life may actually undermine the ability to reap enjoyment from life‘s small pleasures.
... our research demonstrates that a simple reminder of wealth produces the same deleterious effects as actual wealth, suggesting that perceived access to pleasurable experiences may be sufficient to impair everyday savoring. (Quoidbach et al., 2010)
This perspective is consistent with the intriguing theoretical notion that hedonic adaptation may occur not only in response to past experiences, but also in response to anticipated future experiences (Frederick & Loewenstein, 1999).
Our studies provide a novel contribution by demonstrating that the emotional benefits that money gives with one hand (i.e., access to pleasurable experiences), it takes away with the other by undercutting the ability to relish the small delights of daily living.
... experimentally exposing participants to a reminder of wealth produced the same deleterious effect on savoring as did actual individual differences in wealth.
(Quoidbach et al., 2010)
Across nations, placing a higher importance on money is associated with lower well-being (Kirkcaldy, Furnham, & Martin, 1998).
(Diener & Seligman, 2004)
Financial aspirations are bad for family life (and the quality of interpersonal relationships is a strong predictor of happiness).
The negative consequences [of financial aspirations] were particularly severe for the domain of family life; the stronger the goal for financial success, the lower the satisfaction with family life, regardless of household income.
(Nickerson et al., 2003)
Don’t live ‘high’.
Not only materialism, but wealth itself has been found in a few studies to produce negative effects. Hagerty (2000) found that when personal income was statistically controlled, individuals living in higher-income areas in the United States were lower in happiness than people living in lower-income areas. (Diener & Seligman, 2004)
This suggests that wealthy individuals are fortunate if they live in middle-class areas rather than in wealthy enclaves.
The negative effects of wealthy communities might partly be explained by their higher materialism (Stutzer, in press).
(Diener & Seligman, 2004)
(Perhaps the more important point here is that you must surround yourself with low-materialism people, which means surrounding yourself with happy people, since materialism correlates negatively with happiness. A caveat to the advice of living in middle class areas if wealthy: the presence of a wealthy neighbor can make people more materialistic; it makes them aspire for more. A wealthy person can make his less wealthy neighbors less happy. See below.)
Avoid conspicuous consumption.
The ‘relative income hypothesis’ was formulated and econometrically tested by James Duesenberry (1949), who posited an asymmetric structure of externalities. People look upwards when making comparisons. Aspirations thus tend to be above the level already reached. Wealthier people impose a negative external effect on poorer people, but not vice versa. Fred Hirsch (1976), in his book Social Limits to Growth, emphasised the role of relative social status by calling attention to ‘positional goods’ which, by definition, cannot be augmented, because they rely solely on not being available to others. This theme was taken up by Robert Frank (1985, 1999), who argued that the production of positional goods in the form of luxuries, such as exceedingly expensive watches or yachts, is a waste of productive resources, as overall happiness is thereby decreased rather than increased.
(Frey & Stutzer, 2002)
(This relates to the recommendation to associate with happy people — farther down.)
More Recommendations
WORK SATISFACTION
Coping with Stress: React pragmatically rather than emotionally.
Coping can be divided into two broad engagements – either to trigger the individual to approach the problem or to regulate the emotional reactions arising from the challenge at hand (Andersson & Willebrand 2003). The literature typically differentiates two broad strategies of coping (for a review, see Lazarus & Folkman 1984). First, problem-based coping refers to a cognitively-based response behaviour that includes efforts to alleviate stressful circumstances. This coping strategy includes defining the problem, generating alternative solutions, determining the costs and benefits of such solutions, and actions taken to solve the problem. Second, emotion-based coping involves behavioural responses to regulate the affective consequences of stressful events, which may include avoidance, minimisation and distancing oneself from the problem (Lazarus & Folkman 1984).
It seems that problem-based coping strategies are more instrumental than emotion-based ones for attaining successful entrepreneurial outcomes. This implies that entrepreneurs who are more inclined toward emotion-based coping could be trained to employ more problem-based coping, since coping can be learned just like any other competence.
(Drnovšek et al., 2010)
Leaders and Entrepreneurs: Don’t take on too many business partners. (See also AUTONOMY below)
… entrepreneurs who had lower perceived role centrality and were part of a larger founding team were more inclined to use emotion-based coping than those who started their venture in smaller teams. We believe these insights can help in training entrepreneurs in the development of effective coping strategies. Individuals with perceived high centrality of their entrepreneurial role are more likely to effectively engage in coping to optimise their venture”s performance and their own psychological well being.
(Drnovšek et al., 2010)
Prefer the ‘approach’ path instead of the ‘avoid’ path.
It is good for your well-being to work towards achieving something, rather than preventing something from happening.
[One] concern is whether one’s goal activities are characterized by approach or avoidance motivational systems. Elliot & Sheldon (1997), for example, classified goals as approach or avoidance and then examined the effects of goal progress over a short-term period. Pursuit of avoidance goals was associated with both poorer goal progress and with lower well-being. Elliot et al (1997) similarly showed that people whose personal goals contained a higher proportion of avoidance had lower SWB [Subjective Well Being]. They also demonstrated the association between neuroticism and avoidance goals, but showed that the impact of avoidance regulation was evident even when controlling for neuroticism. Carver & Scheier (1999) also presented research linking approach goals (positively) and avoidance goals (negatively) to well-being outcomes.
(Ryan & Deci, 2001)
AUTONOMY: Make a point of prefering autonomous goals rather than heteronomous goals (goals imposed/expected by others).
Another actively researched issue concerns how autonomous one is in pursuing goals. SDT in particular has taken a strong stand on this by proposing that only self-endorsed goals will enhance well-being, so pursuit of heteronomous goals, even when done efficaciously, will not. The relative autonomy of personal goals has, accordingly, been shown repeatedly to be predictive of well-being outcomes controlling for goal efficacy at both between-person and within-person levels of analysis (Ryan & Deci 2000). Interestingly this pattern of findings has been supported in cross-cultural research, suggesting that the relative autonomy of one’s pursuits matters whether one is collectivistic or individualistic, male or female (e.g. V Chirkov & RM Ryan 2001; Hayamizu 1997, Vallerand 1997).
Sheldon & Elliot (1999) developed a self-concordance model of how autonomy relates to well-being. Self-concordant goals are those that fulfill basic needs and are aligned with one’s true self. These goals are well-internalized and therefore autonomous, and they emanate from intrinsic or identified motivations. Goals that are not self-concordant encompass external or introjected motivation, and are ei- ther unrelated or indirectly related to need fulfillment. Sheldon & Elliot found that, although goal attainment in itself was associated with greater well-being, this effect was significantly weaker when the attained goals were not self-concordant. People who attained more self-concordant goals had more need-satisfying experi- ences, and this greater need satisfaction was predictive of greater SWB. Similarly, Sheldon & Kasser (1998) studied progress toward goals in a longitudinal design, finding that goal progress was associated with enhanced SWB and lower symp- toms of depression. However, the impact of goal progress was again moderated by goal concordance. Goals that were poorly integrated to the self, whose focus was not related to basic psychological needs, conveyed less SWB benefits, even when achieved.
(Ryan & Deci, 2001)
… freely chosen activities increase happiness, while obligatory activities lower it (Csikszentmihalyi & Hunter, 2003).
(Aaker et al., 2010)
... we find additional evidence that entrepreneurs also derive utility from things other than financial success. In particular, the achievement of independence and creativity is highly correlated with start-up satisfaction.
... our results indicate that forcing people into situations when they cannot choose among alternatives is likely to result in significant utility losses, independent of other factors.
(Block & Koellinger, 2009)
AUTONOMY: Make sure you have spare discretionary time — even at financial cost.
having spare time and perceiving control over how to spend that time (i.e. discretionary time) has been shown to have a strong and consistent effect on life satisfaction and happiness, even controlling for the actual amount of free time one has (Eriksson, Rice, & Goodin, 2007; Goodin, Rice, Parpo, & Eriksson, 2008).
Therefore, increase your discretionary time, even if it requires monetary resources. And if you can't afford to, focus on the present moment, breathe more slowly, and spend the little time that you have in meaningful ways.
(Aaker et al., 2010)
Be passionate, but don’t obsess. “Passion Does Make a Difference to People’s Well-Being” (Philippe, Vallerand, & Lavigne, 2009)
Key terms: hedonic well-being; eudaimonic well-being
Recent research has begun to distinguish two aspects of subjective well-being. Emotional [hedonic] well-being refers to the emotional quality of an individual’s everyday experience—the frequency and intensity of ex- periences of joy, stress, sadness, anger, and affection that make one’s life pleasant or unpleasant. Life evaluation [eudaimonic well-being] refers to the thoughts that people have about their life when they think about it.
(Kahneman & Deaton, 2010)
The results of two studies provided support for the idea that being harmoniously passionate for an activity contributes significantly to both hedonic and eudaimonic well-being, while being obsessively passionate or not being passionate for any activity does not contribute to well-being at all.
Indeed, merely engaging in a given activity without passion (i.e. being non-passionate) led to the lowest scores on both hedonic and eudaimonic well-being in Study 1 and to the highest decreases in vitality in Study 2 (although no significant differences were found between non-passionate and obsessively passionate people in these studies).
harmoniously passionate people scored significantly higher than obsessively passionate and non-passionate people on hedonic and eudaimonic well-being (Study 1).
only harmoniously passionate people showed a significant increase in vitality over a 1-year period, while obsessively passionate participants showed a slight decrease and non- passionate participants an even larger decrease (Study 2).
only harmonious passion positively predicts well-being over time, while obsessive passion is either negatively associated or unrelated to it (Rousseau & Vallerand, 2003, 2008; Vallerand et al., 2008, Study 2; Vallerand et al., 2007, Studies 1 and 2).
it would appear that an obsessively passionate or non-passionate engagement does not contribute to well-being, and may even have a cost, as shown by the decreases in vitality found in Study 2 for obsessively passionate and non-passionate people.
(Philippe et al., 2009)
Do work that you enjoy doing. Flow.
the accomplishment of goals and the ability to be lost in a task (Csikszentmihalyi and Csikszentmihalyi 1988) seem to be correlated with happiness.
(Nicolao, Irwin, & Goodman, 2009)
Sheldon and Lyubomirsky (2007) have posited that there is much room for improvement in one’s happiness. They suggest that while the largest part of our level of happiness is preset by our genetic endowment (around 50%), some 40 per cent is still modifiable (the last 10% is due to uncontrollable circumstances) and the best way to do this is through what they call “intentional activity engagement”.
They recommend engaging in interesting, fun activities that fit one’s personality and dispositions, that can vary in content, and that are not merely engaged in as a routine but when people feel like doing it. We agree with such a recommendation, especially as Sheldon and Lyubomirsky’s definition of intentional activity is rather close to that of harmonious passion.
(Philippe et al., 2009)
In Kasser’s view, the secret to SWB is meeting one’s intrinsic needs, which means pursuing intrinsic goals out of an intrinsic motivation. In this way, it is similar to Csikszentmihalyi’s (1999) view that happiness stems from “flow” experiences, which are also intrinsically motivated. I contend that the shift toward individualistic cultures that accompanies economic development helps people create life-styles that are consis- tent with their preferences and aptitudes (Veenhoven, 1999), and in so doing pursue their intrinsic needs.
(Ahuvia, 2002)
Set goals that are reasonably challenging and reasonably achievable.
One issue concerns the level of challenge posed by one’s goals. When life goals are nonoptimally challenging—either too easy or too difficult—positive affect [emotional well-being] is lower (Csikszentmihalyi & Csikszentmihalyi 1988). Low expectations of success have also been associated with high negative affect (Emmons 1986),
(Ryan & Deci, 2001)
Prefer intrinsic (vs. extrinsic) goals
Definition:
Psychologists make a distinction between two important kinds of goals—intrinsic and extrinsic. Intrinsic goals involve activities and projects that are personally rewarding and meaningful, and that satisfy people's basic needs for competence, relatedness, and autonomy (Kasser & Ryan, 1993, 1996; see Ryan & Deci, 2000, for a review). By contrast, extrinsic goals involve strivings for fame, money, or favorable outward appearances. Research suggests that positive events generated by the fulfillment of intrinsic goals (e.g., making purchases for others rather than yourself) produce more happiness than those generated by extrinsic goals (Dunn, Aknin & Norton, 2008; see also Kasser, 2002; cf. Dunn et al., 2011).
(Chancellor & Lyubomirsky, 2011)
Because high aspirations undermine the benefits of a positive change, are people simply better off with few goals and lowered aspirations? Not necessarily. Ambitious goals held before beginning a new venture motivate people to work harder on that venture and improve their overall performance (Heath, Larrick & Wu, 1999). Individuals would, however, be happier if they focused their monies and efforts on meaningful, intrinsic goals and abandoned extrinsic ones.
Extrinsic goals undermine well-being in several ways. First, by their very nature, extrinsic goals do not satisfy people's basic needs directly, if at all. Instead, much like an addiction (Koob & Le Moal, 2001), such goals lead to ever-increasing desires for psychologically unfulfilling commodities (Myers, 2000). Second, extrinsic goals appear to be incompatible with close, meaningful relationships. Those who pursue extrinsic goals report poorer relationships (Kasser & Ryan, 2001). Indeed, even being reminded of money, as Dunn and colleagues (2011) mention, can cause people to be less prosocial and less generous (Vohs, Mead & Goode, 2006), as well as to be perceived as less friendly and likable by others (Vohs, 2010).
... over-reliance on external contingencies such as becoming famous, wealthy, or attractive may lead to fragile self-worth (Sheldon, Ryan, Deci & Kasser, 2004). For example, a student seeking a law degree from a prestigious and pricey school with the aim of gaining peer respect might become hopelessly depressed if not admitted. Finally, due to limits of attention, time, and energy, extrinsic goals can lead to the neglect of intrinsic pursuits, which are associated with higher well-being (Vohs et al., 2006).
An entrepreneur investing in a new company with the aim of striking it rich might neglect his true interests and hobbies to invest all his energy into his business, and thus miss the need-satisfying personal growth, flow, and joy derived from his more authentic pursuits.
Fittingly expressing the futility and unhappiness wrapped up in pursuing extrinsic goals, a notorious New York tabloid editor confessed that he was “part of that strange race of people aptly described as spending their lives doing things they detest to make money they don't want to buy things they don't need to impress people they dislike” (Gauvreau, 1941). As Benjamin Franklin well knew, money is best directed to goals that directly satisfy personal needs such as affiliation, autonomy, and competence rather than expensive pursuits that are unfulfilling and distracting in the end.
In contrast, intrinsic goals, such as building close relationships, making new self-discoveries, and investing in the community, directly activate feelings of satisfaction and con- tentment, which are more likely to be appreciated and less likely to be taken for granted. Dunn and colleagues (2011) rightfully emphasize the link between generosity and well- being, recommending that, to follow the example of Warren Buffett, people spend their money on others rather them themselves.
Intrinsic goals can also trigger “upward spirals”— for example, streams of positive moods and prosocial behavior that gain momentum and reinforce one another as they unfold (Lyubomirsky, King, & Diener, 2005; Norton, Dunn, Aknin & Sandstrom, 2009; Otake, Shimai, Tanaka-Matsumi, Otsui & Fredrickson, 2006).
(Chancellor & Lyubomirsky, 2011)
MATERIALISM AND PURCHASING
The Hedonic Treadmill: We adapt to life changes. Many things that give pleasure will soon cease to do so, thereby driving us to seek more, and more…
The “pursuit of happiness” is central to the U.S. worldview, yet the very expression also illustrates a paradox of that worldview: Perhaps when one [naively] pursues happiness too single-mindedly, one fails to notice and take advantage of what one already has. In other words, [naively] striving for ever greater happiness may set one on a hedonic treadmill to nowhere. (More on this below)
(Sheldon & Lyubomirsky, 2012)
Prefer experiential purchases; avoid materialistic goals. It is better to collect (positive) experiences than to collect things.
(But do not keep repeating the same positive experience, lest hedonic adaptation set in quicker. See "Stretching Happiness" farther down.)
Experiential activities are inherently more social (Caprariello & Reis, 2010; Van Boven & Gilovich, 2003) and for this reason fulfill the psychological need for relatedness (Howell & Hill, 2009).
(Howell et al., 2012)
Discretionary experiential purchases ostensibly foster more social contact than discretionary material purchases (Millar & Thomas 2009; Van Boven, 2005), which is a key component to happiness (Argyle, 2001).
Research has demonstrated that people are happier with experiential purchases compared to material items.
Experiential purchases are more central to positive self-identity than material purchases.
Further, experiential purchases may satisfy the personal needs of development and growth more than material acquisitions (Kasser & Ryan, 1996).
(Thomas, 2010)
... we show that on average the most happiness obtained through purchasing is likely to be obtained through experiential purchases that turn out well.
... positive social interaction is a major source of happiness; many experiential purchases involve activities with other people, including family.
(Nicolao et al., 2009)
Materialism might lead to lower well-being because materialistic people tend to downplay the importance of social relationships and to have a large gap between their incomes and material aspirations (Solberg, Diener, & Robinson, 2004).
(Diener & Seligman, 2004)
Several studies have documented that a materialistic lifestyle is associated with diminished subjective well-being.
... consistent with previous research, we found that materialism is negatively correlated with life satisfaction (Belk 1984, 1985; Burroughs and Rindfleisch 2002; Christopher et al. 2007; Ryan and Dziurawiec 2001; Wright and Larsen 1993).
... in line with previous research (Christopher and Schlenker 2004; Chris- topher et al. 2009). High materialistic consumers experience negative emotions more frequently than low materialistic consumers.
(Hudders & Pandelaere, 2011)
... we administered three widely used measures of a materialistic value orientation to 92 business students in Singapore. As expected, those students who had strongly internalized materialistic values also reported lowered self-actualization, vitality and happiness, as well as increased anxiety, physical symptomatology, and unhappiness. (Kasser & Ahuvia, 2002)
past research demonstrating that materialistic values are associated with experiences of general and existential insecurity (Pyszczynski et al., 1997; Rindfleisch et al., 2009).
(Howell et al., 2012)
... positive experiences not only live on in memories but also lend themselves to even more positive reinterpretations over time as the negative aspects of them fade
(Nicolao et al., 2009)
... when security needs are met, it may be more adaptive to broaden one’s experience and acquire new knowledge, skills, and relationships that often accompany experiential purchases. These experiences, if they do not arouse competing security concerns, may then provide increased SWB with accompanying reductions in feelings of anxiety and insecurity, encouraging further experiential purchases, and resulting in the ‘upward spiral’ depicted in our model. In this way, the benefits of an experiential purchasing tendency may accrue over a lifetime and individuals may develop stable purchasing habits.
(Howell et al., 2012)
In sum, evidence suggests that when looking to spend money, the most satisfying pursuits should involve learning new skills (e.g., mastering a new instrument or learning a foreign language), spending time with others (e.g., taking out one's family to dinner or having coffee with a friend), or doing something good for someone else (e.g., buying Christmas decorations for an elderly neighbor or sending a care package to a sick friend).
(Chancellor & Lyubomirsky, 2011)
We provide evidence that this purchase type by valence interaction is driven by the fact that consumers adapt more slowly to experiential purchases than to material purchases, leading to both greater happiness and greater unhappiness for experiential purchases.
adaptation happens more quickly for material purchases than for experiential purchases.
(Nicolao et al., 2009)
Don’t engage in ‘comparison shopping.’ And don’t place much stock in the happiness potential of any one positive change.
Comparison shopping makes us aware of previously unimportant differences and makes us forget the salient qualities of what we want.
Sites like [bizrate.com] offer consumers the opportunity to search for everything [...], comparing a vast range of available options within a given category. [...] Recent research suggests that comparison shopping may sometimes come at a cost. By altering the psychological context in which decisions are made, comparison shopping may distract consumers from attributes of a product that will be important for their happiness, focusing their attention instead on attributes that distinguish the available options.
Another problem with comparison shopping is that the comparisons we make when we are shopping are not the same comparisons we will make when we consume what we shopped for (Hsee, Loewenstein, Blount, & Bazerman, 1999; Hsee & Zhang, 2004).
One of the dangers of comparison shopping, then, is that the options we don't choose typically recede into the past and are no longer used as standards for comparison.
A similar process is likely to unfold in the real estate market. Before purchasing a home, people typically attend scores of open houses and viewings, scrutinizing spec sheets for information about each property's features. Through this process of comparison shopping, the features that distinguish one home from another may come to loom large, while their similarities fade into the background. As a result, home buyers might over- estimate the hedonic consequences of living in a big, beautiful house in a great location versus a more modest home, leading them to take out a larger loan than they can truly afford (potentially sowing the seeds for a nationwide financial crisis).
This suggests that consumers who expect a single purchase to have a lasting impact on their happiness might make more realistic predictions if they simply thought about a typical day in their life.
Conclusion When asked to take stock of their lives, people with more money report being a good deal more satisfied [eudamonic well being]. But when asked how happy they are at the moment, people with more money are barely different than those with less [hedonic well being] (Diener, Ng, Harter, & Arora, 2010). This suggests that our money provides us with satisfaction when we think about it, but not when we use it. That shouldn't happen. Money can buy many, if not most, if not all of the things that make people happy, and if it doesn't, then the fault is ours. We believe that psychologists can teach people to spend their money in ways that will indeed increase their happiness, and we hope we've done a bit of that here.
(Dunn et al., 2011)
When people consider the impact of any single factor on their well-being—not only income—they are prone to exaggerate its importance. We refer to this tendency as the focusing illusion.
(Kahneman, 2006)
'Follow the herd.' (Dunn et al., 2011)
Research suggests that the best way to predict how much we will enjoy an experience is to see how much someone else enjoyed it. In one study, Gilbert, Killingsworth, Eyre, and Wilson (2009) asked women to predict how much they would enjoy a speed date with a particular man. Some of the women were shown the man's photograph and autobiography, while others were shown only a rating of how much a previous woman had enjoyed a speed date with the same man a few minutes earlier. Although the vast majority of the participants expected that those who were shown the photograph and autobiography would make more accurate predictions than those who were shown the rating, precisely the opposite was the case. Indeed, relative to seeing the photograph and autobiography, seeing the rating reduced inaccuracy by about 50%. It appears that the 17th century writer François de La Rochefoucauld was correct when he wrote: “Before we set our hearts too much upon anything, let us first examine how happy those are who already possess it.”
(Dunn et al., 2011)
INTERPERSONAL
Socialize — with the right people.
... the effects of wealth are not large, and they are dwarfed by other influences, such as those of personality and social relationships.
(Diener & Seligman, 2004)
... it is not only whether you spend your time with others that influences your happiness, but also who you spend your time with. Interaction partners associated with the greatest happiness levels include friends, family, and significant others, whereas bosses and co-workers tend to be associated with the least happiness (Kahneman et al., 2004).
social leisure activities contribute more to happiness than solitary ones (Reyes-Garcia et al., 2009).
Furthermore, people who frequently engage in social activities experience higher levels of happiness than people who participate in social activities less often (Lloyd & Auld, 2002), and being with others typically improves the quality of an experience (whereas being alone makes most people sad, lonely, or both; Csikszentmihalyi & Larson, 1984; Lewinsohn, Sullivan, & Grosscup, 1982).
(Aaker et al., 2010)
Compared with the less happy groups, the happiest respondents did not exercise significantly more, participate in religious activities significantly more, or experience more objectively defined good events. No variable was sufficient for happiness, but good social relations were necessary.
Our findings suggest that very happy people have rich and satisfying social relationships and spend little time alone relative to average people. […] In contrast, unhappy people have social relationships that are significantly worse than average.
(Diener & Seligman, 2002)
Income and education are more closely related to life evaluation, but health, care giving, loneliness, and smoking are relatively stronger predictors of daily emotions.
(Kahneman & Deaton, 2010)
Associate with happy people.
... research has also shown that our relationships with weak ties, and even strangers, can affect our happiness. Using a large-scale, longitudinal dataset, Fowler and Christakis [5] suggested that happiness spreads throughout social networks,extending up to three degrees of separation: a person becomes happier if their friend’s friend’s friend becomes happier, even if they don’t know that person.
(Aknin, Sandstrom, Dunn, & Norton, 2011b)
People who are surrounded by many happy people and those who are central in the network are more likely to become happy in the future. Longitudinal statistical models suggest that clusters of happiness result from the spread of happiness and not just a tendency for people to associate with similar individuals. A friend who lives within a mile (about 1.6 km) and who becomes happy increases the probability that a person is happy by 25% (95% confidence interval 1% to 57%). Similar effects are seen in coresident spouses (8%, 0.2% to 16%), siblings who live within a mile (14%, 1% to 28%), and next door neighbours (34%, 7% to 70%). Effects are not seen between coworkers. The effect decays with time and with geographical separation.
(Fowler & Christakis, 2008)
Give the people around you opportunities to be generous. Ask them for favors.
You can possibly make people around you happier by allowing them to be kind and generous, and you want to surround yourself with happy people (see above). Aside from making them happier, you will also improve your relationship with them via the Benjamin Franklin effect, which — unintuitively — makes people like you more if you ask them for favors.
Be actively kind (and occasionaly reminisce about your recent acts of kindness).
Subjective happiness was increased simply by counting one’s own acts of kindness for one week.
Happy people became more kind and grateful through the counting kindnesses intervention.
Our results further suggest that a reciprocal relationship may exist between kindness and happiness, as has been shown for gratitude and happiness [see below].
(Otake et al., 2006)
STRETCHING HAPPINESS (fighting hedonic adaptation)
Hedonic adaptation — definition:
The pleasure of success and the ignominy of failure abate with time. So does the thrill of a new sports car, the pain over a failed romance, the delight over a promotion, and the distress of a scary diagnosis. This phenomenon, known as hedonic adaptation (HA), has drawn increasing interest from both psychologists and economists (e.g., Diener, Lucas, & Scollon, 2006; Easterlin, 2006; Frederick & Loewenstein, 1999; Kahneman & Thaler, 2006; Lucas, 2007a; Lyubomirsky, 2011; Lyubomirsky, Sheldon, & Schkade, 2005; Wilson & Gilbert, 2008).
(Sheldon & Lyubomirsky, 2012)
Choose smaller, more frequent successes rather than larger ones.
Even big positive changes can get old fast, and soon stop bringing happiness.
...every one of the published studies evidences fairly rapid and apparently complete adaptation to positive changes. The most widely-cited study is that of Brickman and his colleagues (1978), who reported that lottery winners were no happier up to 18 months after the news than those who had experienced no windfall.
(Sheldon & Lyubomirsky, 2012)
Go for variety and surprise. Don’t keep doing the same thing.
...variable stimuli resist adaptation more than do unchanging stimuli (see also Wilson & Gilbert, 2008).
(Chancellor & Lyubomirsky, 2011)
...these findings support the notion that variety and surprise spice up life in ways that sustain well-being (Sheldon et al., in press; Sheldon & Lyubomirsky, 2006, 2009; Wilson, Centerbar, Kermer, & Gilbert, 2005)”
(Sheldon & Lyubomirsky, 2012)
Savor the anticipation. Delay consumption. Actively anticipate good experiences.
Research in the field of neuroscience has shown that the part of the brain responsible for feeling pleasure, the mesolimbic dopamine system, can be activated when merely thinking about something pleasurable, such as drinking one's favorite brand of beer (McClure, Li, Tomlin, Cypert, Montague, & Montague, 2004) or driving one's favorite type of sports car (Erk, Spitzer, Wunderlich, Galley, & Walter, 2002).
... the brain sometimes enjoys anticipating a reward more than receiving the reward (Loewenstein, 1987; Berns, McClure, Pagnoni, & Montague, 2001).
... the pleasure derived from window shopping for a dress may exceed the pleasure from actually acquiring the dress.
(Aaker et al., 2010)
(Perhaps the above can inform the discourse on the [ir]rationality of lotteries.)
Divide positive experiences into smaller pleasures, if possible.
Dividing consumption into smaller doses and separating it out over time can multiply [the pleasure of] “first bites,” and subsequently, the enjoyment. Savoring a chocolate bar could be as simple as dividing it into squares and eating one piece per day, instead of devouring it all in a single sitting. Research supports the idea that breaks are beneficial for positive experiences, such as enjoying a television program, but detrimental for negative experiences, such as enduring a dental drill (Nelson, Meyvis & Galak, 2009).
(Chancellor & Lyubomirsky, 2011)
Dividing into smaller doses also increases the amount of pleasurable anticipation. See previous subsection.
Corollary: Conclude negative experiences as soon as possible.
Don’t "think about it tomorrow.” Prolongation increases the effect of both negative and positive experiences, and bad is stronger than good:
Although the same hedonic adaptation process is involved in both positive and negative experiences, an important asymme- try exists between the two that further complicates efforts to remain happy, especially if a positive change comes at a high financial cost. To sum up almost two decades of research, bad is stronger than good (Baumeister, Bratslavsky, Finkenauer & Vohs, 2001; see also Taylor, 1991), or as Einstein quipped, “Put your hand on a hot stove for a minute, and it seems like an hour. Sit with a pretty girl for an hour, and it seems like a minute.” [...] positive changes are weaker than negative changes, and that their effects also evaporate more quickly (e.g., Nezlek & Gable, 2001; Sheldon, Ryan & Reis, 1996; see also Oishi, Diener, Choi, Kim-Prieto & Choi, 2007).
(Chancellor & Lyubomirsky, 2011)
Make a point of avoiding experiences that make you feel bad.
Well-being is about more than just frequently feeling good—it is also about infrequently feeling bad (Diener, Suh, Lucas & Smith, 1999).
All else being equal, the elimination of negative experiences could provide a three- to five-fold hedonic return on investment over the creation of positive experiences, due to positive/negative asymmetry (e.g., David, Green, Martin & Suls, 1997; Fredrickson & Losada, 2005; Gottman, 1994).
(Chancellor & Lyubomirsky, 2011)
APPRECIATION
Be grateful. Count your blessings (literally). Recycle happiness. Reminisce about good experiences.
A number of experiments have demonstrated that the regular practice of gratitude—a practice closely related to and often indistinguishable from appreciation and savoring—brings about significant increases in well-being when performed over the course of 1 to 12 consecutive weeks. For example, relative to performing neutral activities, the intentional and effortful practice of “counting one's blessings” once a week (Emmons & McCullough, 2003; Froh, Sefick & Emmons, 2008; Lyubo- mirsky, Sheldon, & Schkade, 2005) or penning appreciation letters to individuals who have been kind and meaningful (Boehm, Lyubomirsky, & Sheldon, in press; Lyubomirsky, Dickerhoof, Boehm, & Sheldon, in press; Seligman, Steen, Park & Peterson, 2005) has been shown to produce increases in happiness for as long as 6 months.
(Chancellor & Lyubomirsky, 2011)
Think of counterfactuals. (“If I didn’t have this, what do I lose?”)
Another cognitive exercise that directs attention toward existing positive changes or events is counterfactual thinking. This strategy involves mentally subtracting a purchased positive experience from ever having taken place, and enumerating all the subsequent blessings that also would have disappeared (Koo, Algoe, Wilson, & Gilbert, 2008).
(Chancellor & Lyubomirsky, 2011)
Breathe deeply. Expand your time — by slowing down.
[People feel less rushed and hurried when they] simply breathe more deeply. In one study, subjects who were instructed to take long and slow breaths (vs. short and quick ones) for 5 minutes not only felt there was more time available to get things done, but also perceived their day to be longer.
(Aaker et al., 2010)
Stay in the present.
One possible benefit of being present-focused is that thinking about the present moment (vs. the future) slows down the perceived passage of time, allowing people to feel less rushed and hurried (Rudd & Aaker, 2010).
(Aaker et al., 2010)
OPTIMAL HAPPIFICATION
Actively want to be happier. Motivation and investment matter.
First, and most important, we found that to become happier, people need both a will and a proper way. The will can come from motivation, expectations, and diligence. The proper way comes from performing the “right” activity, not merely a placebo. Accordingly, we found that motivation and investment in becoming a happier person matters. That is, expressing gratitude and optimism did not generally increase well-being unless a person was truly cognizant of the exercises’ purpose and motivated to improve his or her happiness. Second, effortful pursuit of happiness activities was found to be important to improving and maintaining well- being.
... happiness interventions are more than just placebos, but […] they are most successful when participants know about, endorse, and commit to the intervention.
According to our model of well-being change (Lyubomirsky, Sheldon, et al., 2005; Sheldon & Lyubomirsky, 2004), sustainable increases in happiness are possible, but only if pursued under optimal conditions, such as when people are motivated to perform a positive activity, when they bring to bear effort and persistence, and when the activity is a legitimately efficacious one.
(Lyubomirsky et al., 2011)
Learn about the science of happiness. Internalize the recommendations in this article and in here.
... people often hold incorrect intuitive theories about the determinants of happiness. For instance, they overestimate the impact of specific life events on their experienced well-being with regard to intensity, as well as with regard to duration. (see also Comparison Shopping above)
... four major sources for systematic over- and undervaluation of choice options that can be distinguished: (i) the underestimation of adaptation, (ii) distorted memory of past experiences, (iii) the rationalization of decisions, and (iv) false intuitive theories about the sources of future utility.
(Quoidbach et al., 2010)
Money is an opportunity for happiness, but it is an opportunity that people routinely squander because the things they think will make them happy often don’t.
It is not surprising when wealthy people who know nothing about wine end up with cellars that aren't that much better stocked than their neighbors', and it should not be surprising when wealthy people who know nothing about happiness end up with lives that aren't that much happier than anyone else's.
(Dunn et al., 2011)
EXTRA CONSIDERATIONS
Happiness predicts [future] income.
(Diener & Seligman, 2004)
(^But try not to think of it that way!)
... we found that with all but one specification, initial happiness levels were positively and significantly correlated with future earnings. […] An additional finding is that the effects of initial period happiness on future income and on future happiness seem to be more consistent across all income groups than are the effects of initial period income on either future income and future happiness. The effects of initial period income seem more important for those at higher levels of income.
The studies by psychologists that find that happiness has positive effects on future income also find that these effects are stronger at the higher end of the income scale. See Diener and Biswas-Diener (1999).
(Graham, Eggers & Sukhtankar, 2004)
... higher cheerfulness in the first year of college correlated with higher income 19 years or so later, when respondents reached their late 30s; this effect was greatest for those who came from the most affluent families
(Diener & Seligman, 2004)
It will be easier to stay happy when you become happier
... our findings also dovetail with those of Cohn and Fredrickson (in press) by demonstrating that initial happiness gains can cause a happiness intervention to become self-reinforcing.
(Aknin, Dunn, & Norton, 2011a)
Happiness Interventions Work!
Fordyce (1977, 1983) created an intervention program based on the idea that people's subjective well-being can be increased if they learn to imitate the traits of happy people, such as being organized, keeping busy, spending more time socializing, developing a positive outlook, and working on a healthy personality. Fordyce found that the program produced increases in happiness compared to a placebo control, as ell as compared to participants in conditions receiving only partial information. Most impressive, he found lasting effects of the intervention in follow-up evaluation 9-28 months after the study.
(Diener et al., 2009)
Recently, a number of additional effective interventions on happiness have been reported, ranging from the kindness interventions (Otake, Shimai, Tanaca-Matumi, Otsui, & Fredrickson, 2006) and gratitude interventions (Emmons & McCulough, 2003) to variants of the writing intervention (King, 2001; Lyubomirsky, Sousa, & Dickerhoof, 2006). Recent intervention studies are clearly promising. However, more diverse dependent variables and measuring instruments would be desirabe, as well as explorations of which interventions are most beneficial, and why.
(Diener et al., 2009)
Extra extra: Cultural Differences
Veenhoven (1999) found that among poor countries, individualism was negatively associated with happiness; whereas among richer countries, individualism was positively associated with happiness. This suggests that economic growth is part of a complex system of modernization that needs to be seen holistically. Collectivism may exist in poorer countries because it is highly functional in that environment, but it may give way to more individualism as societies modernize and the needs of those societies change. Overall, individualism/collectivism stands out as an extremely promising construct for explaining differences in national average levels of SWB, when investigated holistically as part of the larger social system (Cummins, 1998; Myers and Diener, 1995).
... economic development increases SWB by creating a cultural environment where individuals make choices to maximize their happiness rather than meet social obligations (Coleman, 1990; Galbraith, 1992; Triandis, 1989; Triandis et al., 1990; Veenhoven, 1999; Watkins and Liu, 1996). This cultural transformation away from obligation and toward the pursuit of happiness is part of a broader transition away from collectivism and toward individualist cultural values and forms of social organization.
Cross-cultural research shows that values like “enjoying life” and leading “an exciting life” are stronger in individualist societies, whereas “social recognition,” “preserving my public image,” being “humble,” and “honoring parents and elders” are particularly strong in collectivist societies (Triandis et al., 1990, p. 1015). There is no more reason to think that people seek social recognition with the ultimate goal of personal happiness, than there is to think that people seek happiness with the ultimate goal of getting others to think well of them for having such a pleasant affect.
(Ahuvia, 2002)
References
Aaker, J. L., Rudd, M., & Mogilner, C. (2010). If Money Doesn’t Make You Happy, Consider Time. Journal of Consumer Psychology, 2011.
Ahuvia, A. C. (2002). Individualism/collectivism and cultures of happiness: A theoretical conjecture on the relationship between consumption, culture and subjective well-being at the national level. Journal of Happiness Studies, 3(1), 23–36. Springer.
Aknin, L. B., Dunn, E. W., & Norton, M. I. (2011a). Happiness Runs in a Circular Motion: Evidence for a Positive Feedback Loop between Prosocial Spending and Happiness. Journal of Happiness Studies, 13(2), 347–355. doi:10.1007/s10902-011-9267-5
Aknin, L. B., Sandstrom, G. M., Dunn, E. W., & Norton, M. I. (2011b). It's the Recipient That Counts: Spending Money on Strong Social Ties Leads to Greater Happiness than Spending on Weak Social Ties. (M. Perc, Ed.)PLoS ONE, 6(2), e17018. doi:10.1371/journal.pone.0017018
Aknin, L. B., Barrington-Leigh, C. P., Dunn, E. W., Helliwell, J. F., Biswas-Diener, R., Kemeza, I., Nyende, P., et al. (2010). Prosocial spending and well-being: cross-cultural evidence for a psychological universal. National Bureau of Economic Research.
Block, J., & Koellinger, P. (2009). I Can't Get No Satisfaction—Necessity Entrepreneurship and Procedural Utility. Kyklos, 62(2), 191–209. doi:10.1111/j.1467-6435.2009.00431.x
Chancellor, J., & Lyubomirsky, S. (2011). Happiness and thrift: When (spending) less is (hedonically) more. Journal of Consumer Psychology, 21(2), 131.
DeVoe, S. E., & House, J. (2012). Time, money, and happiness: How does putting a price on time affect our ability to smell the roses? Journal of Experimental Social Psychology, 48(2), 466–474. doi:10.1016/j.jesp.2011.11.012
Diener, E., Oishi, S., Lucas, R.E. (2009). Subjective Well-Being: The science of happiness and life satisfaction. Oxford Handbook of Positive Psychology, 187-194.
Diener, E., & Seligman, M. P. (2002). Very happy people. Psychological Science, 13(1), 81–84.
Diener, E., & Seligman, M. P. (2004). Beyond money. Psychological science in the public interest, 5(1), 1–31.
Drnovšek, M., Örtqvist, D., & Wincent, J. (2010). The effectiveness of coping strategies used by entrepreneurs and their impact on personal well-being and venture performance. Journal of Economics and Business, 28, 193–220.
Dunn, E. W., Aknin, L. B., & Norton, M. I. (2008). Spending Money on Others Promotes Happiness. Science, 319(5870), 1687–1688. doi:10.1126/science.1150952
Dunn, E. W., Ashton-James, C. E., Hanson, M. D., & Aknin, L. B. (2010). On the Costs of Self-interested Economic Behavior: How Does Stinginess Get Under the Skin? Journal of Health Psychology, 15(4), 627–633. doi:10.1177/1359105309356366
Dunn, E. W., Gilbert, D. T., & Wilson, T. D. (2011). If money doesn“t make you happy, then you probably aren't spending it right. Journal of Consumer Psychology, 21(2), 115.
Fowler, J. H., & Christakis, N. A. (2008). The dynamic spread of happiness in a large social network. BMJ: British medical journal, 337, a2338.
Frey, B. S., & Stutzer, A. (2002). The economics of happiness. World Economics, 3(1), 1–17.
Graham, C., Eggers, A., & Sukhtankar, S. (2004). Does happiness pay?: An exploration based on panel data from Russia. Journal of Economic Behavior & Organization, 55(3), 319–342. Elsevier.
Howell, R. T., Pchelin, P., & Iyer, R. (2012). The preference for experiences over possessions: Measurement and construct validation of the Experiential Buying Tendency Scale. The Journal of Positive Psychology, 7(1), 57–71.
Hudders, L., & Pandelaere, M. (2011). The Silver Lining of Materialism: The Impact of Luxury Consumption on Subjective Well-Being. Journal of Happiness Studies. doi:10.1007/s10902-011-9271-9
Kahneman, D. (2006). Would You Be Happier If You Were Richer? A Focusing Illusion. Science, 312(5782), 1908–1910. doi:10.1126/science.1129688
Kahneman, D., & Deaton, A. (2010). High income improves evaluation of life but not emotional well-being. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences, 107(38), 16489–16493. doi:10.1073/pnas.1011492107
Kasser, T., & Ahuvia, A. (2002). Materialistic values and well-being in business students. European Journal of Social Psychology, 32(1), 137–146. doi:10.1002/ejsp.85
Lyubomirsky, S., Dickerhoof, R., Boehm, J. K., & Sheldon, K. M. (2011). Becoming happier takes both a will and a proper way: An experimental longitudinal intervention to boost well-being. Emotion, 11(2), 391.
Mogilner, C. (2010). The Pursuit of Happiness: Time, Money, and Social Connection. Psychological Science, 21(9), 1348–1354. doi:10.1177/0956797610380696
Nickerson, C., Schwarz, N., Diener, E., & Kahneman, D. (2003). Zeroing in on the Dark Side of the American Dream A Closer Look at the Negative Consequences of the Goal for Financial Success. Psychological Science, 14(6), 531–536.
Nicolao, L., Irwin, J., & Goodman, J. (2009). Happiness for Sale: Do Experiential Purchases Make Consumers Happier than Material Purchases? Journal of Consumer Research, 36(2), 188–198. doi:10.1086/597049
Otake, K., Shimai, S., Tanaka-Matsumi, J., Otsui, K., & Fredrickson, B. L. (2006). Happy People Become Happier through Kindness: A Counting Kindnesses Intervention. Journal of Happiness Studies, 7(3), 361–375. doi:10.1007/s10902-005-3650-z
Philippe, F. L., Vallerand, R. J., & Lavigne, G. L. (2009). Passion does make a difference in people's lives: A look at well-being in passionate and non-passionate individuals. Applied Psychology: Health and Well-Being, 1(1), 3–22.
Quoidbach, J., Dunn, E. W., Petrides, K. V, & Mikolajczak, M. (2010). Money Giveth, Money Taketh Away. Psychological Science, 21(6), 759.
Ryan, R. M., & Deci, E. L. (2001). On happiness and human potentials: A review of research on hedonic and eudaimonic well-being. Annual Review of Psychology, 52(1), 141–166.
Sheldon, K. M., Lyubomirsky, S. (2012).The Challenge of Staying Happier: Testing the Hedonic Adaptation Prevention Model. Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin. doi:10.1177/0146167212436400
Stutzer, A., & Frey, B. S. (2010). Recent advances in the economics of individual subjective well-being. Social Research: An International Quarterly, 77(2), 679–714.
Thomas, R. L. (2010). Mediating and moderating variables between discretionary purchases and happiness. UNLV Theses/Dissertations/Professional Papers/Capstones. Paper 889.
267 comments
Comments sorted by top scores.
comment by Will_Newsome · 2012-04-15T11:52:29.825Z · LW(p) · GW(p)
This isn't a fault of the post per se, but I wish there wasn't so damn much equivocation on the word "happiness". I know what sadness, contempt, contentment, rapture, &c. are—introspectively they strike me as a rather distinct states. But "happiness" means like ten or fifteen different things that are only somewhat related to each other. (FWIW smiling makes me feel bitter-sweet, not happy, so this might be an undue generalization from one example.)
Also, at least many kinds of happiness are measures of value, not ends in themselves, and so chasing after them specifically is getting dangerously close to wireheading or the problems of Goodhart's law more generally.
Replies from: Will_Newsome, Klevador, steven0461, Klevador↑ comment by Will_Newsome · 2012-04-15T12:07:46.302Z · LW(p) · GW(p)
Some feelings that have some "happiness"-nature: joy (piti), rapture (piti), bliss (sukha), loving-kindness (metta), adoration, sadness (paradoxically?), bitter-sweet-ness, exaltation, triumph, relief, a variation on wistfulness related to loving-kindness, power, pleasure, communing with God (maybe rapture/adoration/exaltation hybrid?), sehnsucht (sort of?). There are more but the list at least indicates the variety.
Replies from: None↑ comment by Klevador · 2012-04-15T12:22:26.004Z · LW(p) · GW(p)
Re Equivocation: Good point. The important distinction seems to be between hedonic well-being and eudaimonic well-being.
Found on the web:
Current research on well-being has been derived from two general perspectives: the hedonic approach, which focuses on happiness and defines well-being in terms of pleasure attainment and pain avoidance; and the eudaimonic approach, which focuses on meaning and self-realization and defines well-being in terms of the degree to which a person is fully functioning. These two views have given rise to different research foci and a body of knowledge that is in some areas divergent and in others complementary.
The thrust of this post is mostly for hedonic well-being (or 'experienced happiness').
Replies from: Will_Newsome↑ comment by Will_Newsome · 2012-04-15T13:08:57.859Z · LW(p) · GW(p)
(For the "meaning and self-realization" side of things one should check out transpersonal psychology. Here's an abridged version of William James' "The Varieties of Religious Experience".)
Replies from: Klevador↑ comment by steven0461 · 2012-04-16T00:17:13.200Z · LW(p) · GW(p)
It would be particularly nice to understand what sense of "happiness" people (should) have in mind when they say that happiness is instrumentally useful.
Replies from: Raemon↑ comment by Raemon · 2012-04-21T16:10:53.774Z · LW(p) · GW(p)
When did people say happiness was instrumentally useful? I mean, I think it probably is to a certain extent, but I want happiness explicitly because it's a terminal value, and I don't judge people who place other values higher.
Replies from: Will_Newsome, steven0461↑ comment by Will_Newsome · 2012-05-07T02:05:20.524Z · LW(p) · GW(p)
How do you make the distinction between valuing being happy versus valuing the things that cause you to be happy? I'm worried about happiness-seekers making errors here; I think that at least in some cases a person trying to increase his happiness sounds a lot like an economic planner trying to increase a country's GDP, rather than trying to increase the things that GDP is (perhaps-incorrectly!) seen as an indicator of desirability of. It seems to me that various kinds of happiness are qualia that are outputs of certain motivational architectures which were created by variably egosyntonic genetic/memetic/Hebbian selection pressures aimed at solving not-entirely-motivational problems which might in themselves be valuable to solve. In such cases reifying the goal of being happy qua being happy would risk an unfortunate error. (This is all modulo my confusion about what people usually mean when they talk about "happiness" in general.)
Replies from: Raemon↑ comment by Raemon · 2012-05-07T02:53:30.057Z · LW(p) · GW(p)
There are things I value in addition to being happy. Creating quality art. Contributing to global human flourishing. But I definitely value happiness for its own sake. I don't try to maximize happiness, but there's a certain amount that I need to satisfice on.
I don't know exactly what makes me happy - it's includes "working on fulfilling projects," "having a good social network", "getting exercise", and "having close, intimate friends/romantic-partners". but not necessarily all of those things, all the time.
One important thing I learned last year is that sometimes, something I think of as "important" turns out to be making me unhappy. It's useful to me to look at "total happiness GDP", see when it started going down, and then figure out which variable was the cause.
This year, I started going to a bunch of new meetups, which were individually fun and valuable for my long-term non-happiness goals. But for some reason I became increasingly stressed and unhappy. Eventually I realized that I had forgotten I was an introvert, and even though I enjoy extroverted activities, I need to ensure I get alone time.
I cut back on meetups, and I feel much better now. I appreciate this because I feeling good is good, and also because it means I can get other things done.
Not sure if that explained it very well. I could write multiple pages about how I think about happiness, but if I'm doing that it probably should be a fully-formed post.
↑ comment by steven0461 · 2012-04-21T17:24:36.242Z · LW(p) · GW(p)
Yes, when I claimed that people sometimes say that happiness is instrumentally useful, that was not based on them saying happiness is worth pursuing and me concluding they must therefore think it's instrumentally useful; rather, it was based on them saying happiness is instrumentally useful.
Replies from: Raemon↑ comment by Klevador · 2012-04-15T12:30:24.455Z · LW(p) · GW(p)
As for your second paragraph — I'm not certain, but I think it's rational to treat happiness as a maximand. Is your objection not addressed by the sections "Optimal Happification" and "Happiness Interventions Work!" ?
Replies from: Will_Newsome↑ comment by Will_Newsome · 2012-04-15T12:52:35.197Z · LW(p) · GW(p)
To a significant extent it seems to me to be a question of moral philosophy. But there are also practical objections—for example, I might have missed it, but I don't see "regularly smoke opium" as one of the listed recommendations. As far as increasing happiness goes I hear it's hard to beat heroin. Nonetheless most people who strive for happiness don't go the heroin/painkiller route. I think this says something about the desirability of experienced happiness by itself.
Replies from: TheOtherDave, None, Hul-Gil↑ comment by TheOtherDave · 2012-04-15T16:25:09.558Z · LW(p) · GW(p)
Most people I know believe that heroin (and similar mechanisms) get short-term happiness followed either by long-term unhappiness, or death. So I'm not sure how much their avoidance of that route says about how much they desire happiness by itself, other than that it isn't strictly more important than longevity. (The fact that unhappy people don't always kill themselves suggests that as well.)
Of course, it's tricky inferring causation from correlation. It might be that we believe that about heroin because it reinforces our predisposition to reject experienced happiness as a motivator, for example, whether it's true or not.
Replies from: Hul-Gil↑ comment by Hul-Gil · 2012-04-17T16:46:24.208Z · LW(p) · GW(p)
Most people I know believe that heroin (and similar mechanisms) get short-term happiness followed either by long-term unhappiness, or death.
That's the long and short of it, I think. There is no reason not to use heroin to obtain maximum utility (for one's self), if one a.) finds it pleasurable, b.) can afford it, and c.) is able to obtain pure and measured doses. (Or simply uses pharmaceuticals.) The perceived danger of heroin comes from its price and illegality (uncertain dosage + potentially dangerous impurities), which often results in penury, and overdose or illness, for the user.
People also want "real" happiness, by which I presume they mean happiness resulting from actions like painting a picture, and not happiness induced by chemical... which is silly, since the two feelings are produced by the same neurochemistry and functionally identical (i.e., all happiness is ultimately chemical). (The perceived difference may still bother someone enough that they choose a different route, though, especially if they don't realize they can just paint a picture... on heroin.)
Replies from: TheOtherDave, tog↑ comment by TheOtherDave · 2012-04-17T18:37:49.805Z · LW(p) · GW(p)
Well, you're leaving out any discussion of goals I might have other than pleasure, and how well heroin helps me achieve those goals. One difference between heroin use and painting a picture is that the latter case causes there to be a picture, for example, and I might value the existence of the picture in addition to valuing my neurochemical state.
But, sure, if I can do all the same stuff in the world as well or better while maintaining a heroin habit, then that's not relevant.
Replies from: Hul-Gil↑ comment by Hul-Gil · 2012-04-17T22:18:02.355Z · LW(p) · GW(p)
I was hoping someone would bring that up. You've already given the same answer I would, though: it's not necessarily an either/or scenario like Nozick's "experience machine" concept, so it's possible to have both heroin and pictures, in theory.
↑ comment by Hul-Gil · 2012-04-17T16:49:33.632Z · LW(p) · GW(p)
See my post below; I think this is due to a.) a misunderstanding of the nature of happiness (a thought that chemically-induced happiness is different from "regular" happiness... which is also chemical), b.) a feeling that opium is incredibly dangerous (as it can be), and c.) a misunderstanding of how opium makes you feel - people can say "I know opium makes you happy" without actually feeling/knowing that it does so. That is, their mental picture of how they'd feel if they smoked opium doesn't correspond to the reality, which is - for most people - that it makes them feel much, much better than they would have imagined.
comment by David_Gerard · 2012-04-15T09:31:05.205Z · LW(p) · GW(p)
I felt the urge to upvote this article on a "more please" basis, but actually tl;dr'ed past the content once I'd read the summary. Anyone else?
Replies from: satt, Randaly, Klevador, undermind, army1987, juliawise↑ comment by satt · 2012-04-15T12:53:37.970Z · LW(p) · GW(p)
Yep, me too. I don't think that's a problem, though. The content is practically an annotated bibliography, which needs to be there to substantiate the summary but doesn't need to be read unless you really want to.
Replies from: Klevador↑ comment by Klevador · 2012-04-15T13:11:39.327Z · LW(p) · GW(p)
Still, I argue that you should read the bulk of the post. Reading just the summary may be like just reading the synopsis of a movie (if I may be so hubristic! :) instead of watching it. You 'get' the idea but you don't appreciate it as much, and it doesn't stick with you as much as if you watched it. Less mental associations.
And to be more specific, you will miss, among other things, the supporting argument (aside from the obvious) for why you should make a point of avoiding bad experiences. Perhaps I should have included it in the summary.
↑ comment by Randaly · 2012-04-15T10:19:33.447Z · LW(p) · GW(p)
Evidently almost everybody, since nobody has pointed out the broken link here:
"This research also supports the broaden-and-build theory of positive emotions by demonstrating that higher levels of happiness may expand an individual’s mindset to include thoughts of others."
Which is a pity, because I thought the meat of the post added a lot to the (already completely awesome!) summary.
(Also: there's a broken link.)
ETA: Also, I see a lot of references to "(Aaker et al 2010)" throughout the post- is that the same as "(Aaker, Rudd, & Mogilner, 2010)," which is only cited once?
Replies from: Klevador↑ comment by Klevador · 2012-04-15T11:49:43.111Z · LW(p) · GW(p)
Fixed and fixed! How do you have such sharp eyes.
I thought the meat of the post added a lot to the (already completely awesome!) summary.
Yes, and I don't learn well from outline-summaries only. I imagine that I would not gain much if I had read only the summary up top. The just-acquired lessons would quickly dissipate without the examples and explanations to reinforce them.
Replies from: Randaly↑ comment by Randaly · 2012-04-16T03:50:54.514Z · LW(p) · GW(p)
Thanks- I'm just following whatever extracts I find particularly interesting back to the original papers. (I found the bit about spare time leading to happiness particularly interesting, which is how I found the Aaker reference.)
One more thing: In the sentence "Aside from making them happier, you will also improve your relationship with them via the Benjamin Franklin effect, which — unintuitively — makes people like you more if you ask them for favors.", the link to the wikipedia article on the Ben Franklin Effect links to this:
http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Benjamin_Franklin_Effect
Instead of to the article here:
http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Ben_Franklin_effect
Replies from: Klevador↑ comment by Klevador · 2012-04-16T07:54:26.926Z · LW(p) · GW(p)
Does this mean that outline-summaries in posts like this are a bad idea, given that people can be very impatient?
(BTW, before tl;dr-ing, try breathing deeply first. It may make you feel less impatient :p )
Replies from: David_Gerard, wedrifid↑ comment by David_Gerard · 2012-04-16T10:45:30.894Z · LW(p) · GW(p)
No no, outline summaries are a great idea! Just keep in mind that may be all someone reads ;-)
↑ comment by wedrifid · 2012-04-16T08:22:12.926Z · LW(p) · GW(p)
Does this mean that outline-summaries in posts like this are a bad idea, given that people can be very impatient?
No. I read the outline summary. I wouldn't have read just a wall of text. I may have scrolled through and read the section headings - but that gives me essentially the outline summary.
↑ comment by undermind · 2012-04-17T21:30:15.407Z · LW(p) · GW(p)
I found some of the content in the summary sufficiently noteworthy that I will remember it, regardless of the supporting evidence, and for the rest, the supporting evidence doesn't help. In particular, asking people for favours to give them the opportunity to be kind is a cool idea that is new to me, which I intend to start doing.
↑ comment by A1987dM (army1987) · 2012-04-17T10:19:18.381Z · LW(p) · GW(p)
I read about half of the article and skimmed the rest.
comment by steven0461 · 2012-04-16T00:26:08.865Z · LW(p) · GW(p)
This may be paranoid of me, but I'm always worried that when posts like this use the word "you", people will read it as "you", when they should be reading it as "the average person, who is similar to you to some extent (e.g. in possessing such brain machinery as is humanly universal), and whose properties inform you about your own properties to a degree that depends on background information".
Replies from: steven0461, Will_Newsome↑ comment by steven0461 · 2012-04-16T05:13:02.367Z · LW(p) · GW(p)
It would be pretty neat if we had some happiness research that was disaggregated by such variables as intelligence, cognitive reflectiveness, and introversion. Does anyone know of such research?
Replies from: Klevador↑ comment by Will_Newsome · 2012-04-16T05:05:01.475Z · LW(p) · GW(p)
E.g., I've seen a few studies purporting that "high intelligence" (which IIRC meant like 1.5 SD above average SAT scores) provides substantial protection against common cognitive biases. Yet I've never seen anyone take this into account when discussing "de-biasing".
Replies from: steven0461↑ comment by steven0461 · 2012-04-16T05:09:19.102Z · LW(p) · GW(p)
How would you take that into account? Does high intelligence provide more protection against some biases than others? Can we isolate what aspect of high intelligence provides the protection, and amplify that aspect?
Replies from: Will_Newsome↑ comment by Will_Newsome · 2012-04-16T05:25:24.497Z · LW(p) · GW(p)
I personally wouldn't take it into account at all, because it's H&B research, i.e., untrustworthy and irrelevant to rationality, and also I do not condone trying to "de-bias" oneself. (Pretty sure the H&B consensus agrees with me on the dubious nature of "de-biasing", anyone know if I'm wrong?) Lukeprog might have answers to your questions, IIRC he's the one who sent me the papers in question.
Replies from: steven0461↑ comment by steven0461 · 2012-04-16T05:33:31.765Z · LW(p) · GW(p)
Would you condone trying to de-bias oneself if you thought the research was trustworthy and relevant? That is, do you see an extra reason on top of those reasons not to engage in de-biasing?
Replies from: Will_Newsome↑ comment by Will_Newsome · 2012-04-16T10:33:33.808Z · LW(p) · GW(p)
That is, do you see an extra reason on top of those reasons not to engage in de-biasing?
Yes, the first law of ecology (also known in another aspect as Chesterton's fence). There are exceptions but those exceptions only apply to people with abnormally accurate self models.
Replies from: MichaelVassar↑ comment by MichaelVassar · 2012-04-17T05:02:05.021Z · LW(p) · GW(p)
Why expect unintended consequences to oppose ones preferences? The biases weren't created by processes that cared about your preferences.
Replies from: Jayson_Virissimo↑ comment by Jayson_Virissimo · 2012-04-17T09:20:48.956Z · LW(p) · GW(p)
Why expect unintended consequences to oppose ones preferences? The biases weren't created by processes that cared about your preferences.
Yeah, but our preferences were caused by the same thing as our biases, right? At the very least, shouldn't we expect our preferences to be highly entangled with our biases because of their common origin?
comment by Wei Dai (Wei_Dai) · 2012-04-15T22:00:22.908Z · LW(p) · GW(p)
Don’t do ‘comparison shopping.’
I used to do less comparison shopping than I do now, and would occasionally regret certain purchases. I almost never have such regrets now. And comparison shopping itself feels more like play than work. Does this seem like enough reason to think that the advice doesn't apply to me, or is there something I'm overlooking?
Replies from: Dustin, RobFisher, MaoShan, John_Maxwell_IV, Will_Newsome↑ comment by Dustin · 2012-04-21T15:34:10.056Z · LW(p) · GW(p)
I've commented on this research before. In short, while it's plausible that I may be less happy with purchases made via comparison shopping, I'm overall less happy with the world where I don't do comparison shopping.
Replies from: dlthomas↑ comment by dlthomas · 2012-04-21T15:45:40.434Z · LW(p) · GW(p)
Better still might (mind you, I said "might") be trading with someone else you trust - you do the comparison shopping for them, they do it for you, after communicating your criteria. That way, you get the best option available (or something reasonably close to it) while not eroding your satisfaction with thoughts of what could have been.
↑ comment by RobFisher · 2012-04-19T14:07:50.785Z · LW(p) · GW(p)
See also the section on anticipation: "...the pleasure derived from window shopping for a dress may exceed the pleasure from actually acquiring the dress." I get happiness from the process of comparison shopping. It is part of the anticipation. Perhaps this advice needs further qualification.
↑ comment by John_Maxwell (John_Maxwell_IV) · 2012-04-20T04:58:55.870Z · LW(p) · GW(p)
It makes me uncomfortable to think that I might have made a purchase that was suboptimal, sometimes. So this point I just think things through thoroughly every time; it seems less stressful empirically.
↑ comment by Will_Newsome · 2012-04-16T05:11:01.551Z · LW(p) · GW(p)
And comparison shopping itself seems more like play than work.
Seriously, I often do it just for fun. ("OMG can't wait for Ivy Bridge! It will make counterfactual-me's computer so much faster! /covet")
comment by Alicorn · 2012-04-15T06:50:10.446Z · LW(p) · GW(p)
I think this would do well in Main.
Replies from: wedrifid↑ comment by wedrifid · 2012-04-15T06:52:54.816Z · LW(p) · GW(p)
Yes, it most certainly doesn't belong here. Move it to main please author! (Whereupon Eliezer should promote it.)
Replies from: Klevador↑ comment by Klevador · 2012-04-15T06:59:51.956Z · LW(p) · GW(p)
1 karma point to go :)
eta: I have 19 karma at the moment.
Replies from: wedrifid, Barry_Cotter, SusanBrennan↑ comment by Barry_Cotter · 2012-04-15T11:13:40.476Z · LW(p) · GW(p)
Shit. When I was reading through I suspected you were one of the remote literature researchers because this has the makings of a good literature review article I think.
↑ comment by SusanBrennan · 2012-04-15T12:02:01.036Z · LW(p) · GW(p)
I upvoted your post to a nice round 20. It's a much nicer number than 19 anyway.
Replies from: TheOtherDave↑ comment by TheOtherDave · 2012-04-15T16:16:45.504Z · LW(p) · GW(p)
I'm saddened that it's no longer prime.
Replies from: Danfly↑ comment by Danfly · 2012-04-15T18:05:38.501Z · LW(p) · GW(p)
Upvoting to 31, which is quite a fantastic number, since it is both (aptly) a "happy" prime, as well as a "sexy" prime.
Replies from: Klevador, SusanBrennan↑ comment by Klevador · 2012-04-16T07:41:43.455Z · LW(p) · GW(p)
Explain?
Replies from: Danfly↑ comment by Danfly · 2012-04-16T07:55:17.424Z · LW(p) · GW(p)
Sorry. I probably should have linked happy and sexy. I was saying that the "happy" component fit well with the topic. Sexy was just an added bonus.
To summarize:
If you take a number, sum the squares of its digits to make a new number, then do the same with the next number and it eventually reaches one through that process, it is a "happy" number. "Happy prime" just refers to those prime numbers which are happy.
Demonstration: 3^2+1^2=10 and 1^2+0^2=1
a sexy prime differs from another prime by 6 (in this case; 37).
↑ comment by SusanBrennan · 2012-04-15T18:15:49.623Z · LW(p) · GW(p)
You forgot primorial.
comment by sark · 2012-04-15T19:46:44.095Z · LW(p) · GW(p)
Hi. First of all thanks for the immensely helpful summary of the literature!
Since you have gone through so much of the literature, I was wondering if you have come across any theories about the functional role of happiness?
I'm currently only aware of Kaj Sotala's post some time ago about how happiness regulates risk-taking. I personally think happiness does this because risk-taking is socially advantageous for high status folks. The theory is that happiness is basically a behavioural strategy pursued by those who have high status. As in, happiness is performed, not pursued. Depression and anxiety would be the opposite of happiness. I remember some studies showing how in primates the low status ones exhibit depression-like and anxious behavior.
It may simply be my ignorance of the literature, but it seems strange that all these (otherwise wonderful) empirical investigations into happiness are motivated only by a common folk theory of its function.
Replies from: khafra, Klevador↑ comment by khafra · 2012-04-18T14:50:38.695Z · LW(p) · GW(p)
The outlines of the performance theory seem good, and it feels introspectively correct as well. But if happiness is a high-status marker, why is it unattractive to women?
Replies from: wedrifid↑ comment by wedrifid · 2012-04-18T16:35:44.226Z · LW(p) · GW(p)
The outlines of the performance theory seem good, and it feels introspectively correct as well. But if happiness is a high-status marker, why is it unattractive to women?
I took a look at the paper, and in particular the sample image they include:
My first impression was a lot more attraction to the female 'pride' picture than any of the other female images - while pride in females was found to be highly unattractive. Now I want to determine whether my preferences differ from some norm or whether this picture is an unusual case.
I do allow that much of my preference may have been determined simply due to the combination of hideously unflattering t-shirts and arms being up in the air compensating for that and actually making breasts evident. If giving all the people ghostly shirts was supposed to be some clever attempt to isolate the influence of clothing then it seems somewhat shortsighted. (Mind you if males were consistently not attracted to the 'pride' female despite it being the only one with apparent breasts then that is just all the more significant!)
Replies from: None, army1987, SkyDK, NancyLebovitz, wedrifid, None, Klevador, thomblake, Eliezer_Yudkowsky↑ comment by [deleted] · 2012-04-18T23:36:25.107Z · LW(p) · GW(p)
Were those pictures seriously used in a psychological study? It strikes me as obvious that the 'pride' images would stand out for having much more implied animation. Though I could see attractiveness swinging both ways depending on viewer personality.
Edit: These seem to have been used in the actual study (via). Maybe that really is just an example?
Replies from: RobinZ, wedrifid, Nornagest, Viliam_Bur, NancyLebovitz, John_D↑ comment by RobinZ · 2012-04-19T04:07:37.819Z · LW(p) · GW(p)
Edit: These seem to have been used in the actual study (via). Maybe that really is just an example?
If those are the pictures, it looks an awful lot like they completely failed to control for the identities of the people in the pictures. For example, the "pride" group is better described as the "professional athlete" group.
↑ comment by wedrifid · 2012-04-18T23:40:06.280Z · LW(p) · GW(p)
Were those pictures seriously used in a psychological study?
Yes, these images were even included in the published pdf of it. It would be useful to be able to see the other images that they used. Perhaps this image is an exception to the norm and the author included it rather than the most representative one because he got a crush on cute-pride-chick during the editing process.
↑ comment by Nornagest · 2012-04-20T08:36:46.152Z · LW(p) · GW(p)
These seem to have been used in the actual study (via). Maybe that really is just an example?
Odd. Those look like stock photos, while the ones in the grandparent clearly aren't. I can see either being used pretty readily, but I'm having trouble coming up with a rationale for both.
↑ comment by Viliam_Bur · 2012-04-20T06:51:05.541Z · LW(p) · GW(p)
Similar mistake. Most of "female neutral" pictures contain only the head; "female happy" has more examples with hands etc.; "female pride" is in a sport context; "female shame" has many full-body pictures.
Authors of the study probably never heard about ceteris paribus.
↑ comment by NancyLebovitz · 2012-04-24T08:08:56.683Z · LW(p) · GW(p)
Thanks for tracking down the original images. They seem like much better choices than the pictures in the comment above here.
Just an impression, but I think that something which can make men (and possibly women) attractive isn't pure sadness-- it's sadness which somehow conveys "but the right person can make me happy".
Replies from: John_D↑ comment by John_D · 2013-04-27T20:14:11.013Z · LW(p) · GW(p)
I personally think the original images used in the study are even worse choices, because at least there is some uniformity between displays of emotions taken from the article, which better control for possible confounders.
Now for the actual pics used in the study. In the set of male pics that are supposed to display pride, there seem to be far more pics that convey athleticism or wealth, as others have pointed out. In the happiness pictures, there seem to be far more close-ups and profile pics, with the rest of the body being hidden from the viewer. I would argue that the shame pics are animated in comparison.
Seems like an overall poor study based on these sample of pics, and certainly should not be a recommendation for men to not smile next time they are out in public.
↑ comment by John_D · 2013-04-27T19:54:27.389Z · LW(p) · GW(p)
This study is a little flawed. In the male example, the shame and especially the pride pictures look more animated, as opposed to just standing straight. When you see someone who is happy, are they just standing straight with their arms by their side? No, that is not the posture you would expect. The happiness picture doesn't look like a genuine display of happiness, while the pride and shame pictures, to me at least, convey the type of body language one would expect when seeing those emotions.
I admit I don't have a good alternative explanation for the female pictures, but perhaps a wide smile is just attractive to men regardless of the posture.
↑ comment by A1987dM (army1987) · 2012-04-18T19:57:07.753Z · LW(p) · GW(p)
I thought about, well... what you say in your last paragraph even before reading your last paragraph. Hence, no idea of how to generalize my impression to people wearing ‘normal’ clothes.
Replies from: wedrifid↑ comment by wedrifid · 2012-04-18T20:34:57.505Z · LW(p) · GW(p)
I thought about, well... what you say in your last paragraph
The way the 'prideful' posture emphasizes the breasts?
Replies from: army1987↑ comment by A1987dM (army1987) · 2012-04-19T16:51:42.458Z · LW(p) · GW(p)
Yes.
↑ comment by SkyDK · 2012-04-19T15:03:12.236Z · LW(p) · GW(p)
Nope, pride definitely is more attractive for me due to the enhanced sense of curves. If this is supposed to proof something, I'd be highly suspicious of the results. I'm really bad a judging men, but I figure the pride one to be better there as well. The happy one seems to fake.
↑ comment by NancyLebovitz · 2012-04-24T08:04:51.767Z · LW(p) · GW(p)
I don't find male happiness unattractive in general, but the Happiness Man in the picture has a smile which strikes me as very spooky.
Were those people feeling the actual emotions, or just asked to express them? The man seemed much better at shame (more effect on the body and the face) than the woman.
↑ comment by wedrifid · 2012-04-18T23:13:17.609Z · LW(p) · GW(p)
POLL: Which of the female poses in the image above is the most attractive?
Replies from: wedrifid, wedrifid, wedrifid, wedrifid, wedrifid↑ comment by wedrifid · 2012-04-18T23:17:22.201Z · LW(p) · GW(p)
Karma sink: Hairy man-boobs is the most attractive of the female poses.
Replies from: khafra↑ comment by khafra · 2012-04-20T16:29:10.757Z · LW(p) · GW(p)
I like your idea here, of a "motivated" karma-sink to help discourage unwarranted karma. Very clever.
Replies from: wedrifid, bcoburn↑ comment by wedrifid · 2012-04-21T17:34:22.167Z · LW(p) · GW(p)
I like your idea here, of a "motivated" karma-sink to help discourage unwarranted karma. Very clever.
So 'clever' that at one point it had received more downvotes than the sum of the poll option upvotes. A net karma loss from poll options would have been nigh unprecedented!
↑ comment by bcoburn · 2012-04-21T13:45:58.753Z · LW(p) · GW(p)
I think it's pretty likely this is just a joke, not really some clever tactic
Replies from: army1987↑ comment by A1987dM (army1987) · 2012-04-21T15:12:22.637Z · LW(p) · GW(p)
Most of wedrifid's karma sinks are witty. (Sometimes I'm tempted to upvote them only because of that.)
Replies from: wedrifid↑ comment by wedrifid · 2012-04-21T17:35:41.745Z · LW(p) · GW(p)
Most of wedrifid's karma sinks are witty. (Sometimes I'm tempted to upvote them only because of that.)
At times there have been karma sinks by others that I have actually upvoted. Fortunately such sinks are there to give the option to be karma neutral, not the obligation. :)
↑ comment by [deleted] · 2012-04-18T22:46:21.730Z · LW(p) · GW(p)
I don't know; I'm a lot more attracted to the male pride picture, and there's no breasts in that one.
Replies from: Nisan, wedrifid↑ comment by wedrifid · 2012-04-18T23:07:33.926Z · LW(p) · GW(p)
I don't know; I'm a lot more attracted to the male pride picture, and there's no breasts in that one.
I'm actually more attracted to the male pride picture than I am to the female neutral and shame pictures - despite generally identifying as a heterosexual male. I don't know or much mind whether it is the same kind of attraction in play but it just seems like there is so much more life emanating from those characters, so I feel drawn to them.
↑ comment by Klevador · 2012-04-19T14:44:29.349Z · LW(p) · GW(p)
Something that distorts my assessment of the images is the female's dowdy clothing, unflattering on the female figure except in the pride image. She looks like a shapeless flour sack in the other three pics.
On the male, the shirt seems 'alright', neutral.
↑ comment by Eliezer Yudkowsky (Eliezer_Yudkowsky) · 2012-04-18T22:40:59.894Z · LW(p) · GW(p)
You need some actual poll here, but yes, the pride image seems obviously more attractive. It is possible that the other confounders played a role, but I at least think that I find pride attractive generally.
Replies from: wedrifid, khafra↑ comment by wedrifid · 2012-04-18T22:57:51.622Z · LW(p) · GW(p)
You need some actual poll here
OK.
You need some actual poll here, but yes, the pride image seems obviously more attractive. It is possible that the other confounders played a role, but I at least think that I find pride attractive generally.
Come to think of it if I rate the pictures based on how happy they seem to me at first glance the 'pride' picture still wins out over 'happiness'. That quite possibly speaks primarily to how happy I feel when in the respective poses.
↑ comment by khafra · 2012-04-20T16:31:56.047Z · LW(p) · GW(p)
Pride it is. What we need now is an experimental design to discern whether LWers prefer pride because we're contrarian; because wannabe-rationalists are less threatened by strong, confident women; because we're unusually attracted to prominent breasts; or some other reason.
Replies from: CuSithBell, RobinZ↑ comment by CuSithBell · 2012-04-20T17:15:29.528Z · LW(p) · GW(p)
What we need now is an experimental design to discern whether [...] we're unusually attracted to prominent breasts
Purely out of scientific curiosity, I'm sure.
↑ comment by Klevador · 2012-04-16T07:36:33.484Z · LW(p) · GW(p)
Good question. Unfortunately I tried to focus entirely on 'how to become happier' in researching for this post, although a possible answer to your query is that happiness promotes prosocial behavior and that happiness can be infectious up to three degrees of separation, thereby making everyone more likely to engage in prosocial behavior.
comment by Viliam_Bur · 2012-04-16T14:40:17.909Z · LW(p) · GW(p)
I buy cat food and give it to random cats I meet in the city. This has extremely good cost:benefit ratio for happiness. The food is cheap and I only give each cat a little, but the act of feeding the cat makes me happy for a few hours. Because those cats are not mine, I have no additional costs. Try to beat that! :P
Replies from: TheOtherDave, gwern, John_Maxwell_IV↑ comment by TheOtherDave · 2012-04-16T14:51:52.232Z · LW(p) · GW(p)
I used to take peanuts to a nearby park to feed squirrels, in much the same spirit. It had the additional benefit that I could eat the peanuts myself if I wanted, and it caused passersby to look at me funny (as I would not-infrequently have squirrels sitting on my lap and rummaging curiously through my pockets).
Replies from: ChrisHibbert↑ comment by ChrisHibbert · 2012-04-22T17:38:06.721Z · LW(p) · GW(p)
My significant other keeps a garden, and we have several productive fruit trees that we enjoy getting fruit from. Squirrels take a significant amount of fruit, and cats leave unwelcome surprises in the garden.
We trap squirrels and remove them to county parks. (We don't do anything about the cats.)
Marginally increasing the frequency of squirrels and cats is a negative externality for us. I'm glad you aren't feeding squirrels (or cats) near us.
Replies from: TheOtherDave↑ comment by TheOtherDave · 2012-04-22T21:14:54.046Z · LW(p) · GW(p)
(nods) Sounds like it works out well for both of us.
↑ comment by gwern · 2012-04-16T20:50:39.114Z · LW(p) · GW(p)
I see your one-shot cat food and raise you cat pennies.
↑ comment by John_Maxwell (John_Maxwell_IV) · 2012-04-20T04:55:45.240Z · LW(p) · GW(p)
What city do you live in? I don't think I've ever been in a city that had enough cats for carrying cat food to seem worthwhile.
Replies from: Viliam_Bur↑ comment by Viliam_Bur · 2012-04-20T06:30:11.408Z · LW(p) · GW(p)
Two cats staying on the same place -- one near my home, another near my job. Chance of meeting 30% per cat per day + 1% random encounter. The cat food is dry, so it won't spoil; I keep a small ration in a small box in a pocket of my coat, carrying it is no problem.
(The city is Bratislava, but both my home and work are out of center.)
comment by [deleted] · 2012-04-15T06:16:43.772Z · LW(p) · GW(p)
This is amazing! Well researched. I want to see an article like this on so many topics.
Replies from: MichaelVassar↑ comment by MichaelVassar · 2012-04-17T05:02:36.767Z · LW(p) · GW(p)
Wow. I disagree exactly. It's a data-dump with little insight. Exactly what I don't want to see on LW.
Replies from: Jonathan_Graehl, wedrifid, Hul-Gil, drethelin↑ comment by Jonathan_Graehl · 2012-04-19T07:26:16.251Z · LW(p) · GW(p)
Maybe insight is better, but for people who haven't already studied everything, posts like this save a lot of time and suggest study of things that perhaps they hadn't realized were there.
↑ comment by wedrifid · 2012-04-19T08:39:16.521Z · LW(p) · GW(p)
Wow. I disagree exactly. It's a data-dump with little insight. Exactly what I don't want to see on LW.
"Insight" sounds altogether too much like "Speculative Just So bullshit".
These are actual empirical findings pertaining to the expected outcomes for executing given behaviors and references to the evidence they are based on. The point isn't to gain 'insight', and any analysis of the data would be best as an investigation in more detail of what the precise indications of the data are, how the indicated behaviors can be most usefully executed and whether any of the summaries given of the findings (and even the findings expressed in the abstracts) are the correct interpretation of the data.
↑ comment by Hul-Gil · 2012-04-19T07:52:03.765Z · LW(p) · GW(p)
I would have liked some thoughts on/insight into the data posted as well; but all the same, summaries like this, that gather a lot of related but widely-dispersed information together, are very useful (especially as a quick reference or overview, or, as Jonathan says below, as a starting point for further research), and I definitely wouldn't mind seeing more of them.
↑ comment by drethelin · 2012-04-17T05:12:44.515Z · LW(p) · GW(p)
http://lesswrong.com/lw/a60/quantified_health_prize_results_announced/5wq7
Replies from: Klevador↑ comment by Klevador · 2012-04-17T07:05:20.424Z · LW(p) · GW(p)
http://lesswrong.com/lw/bdo/rationality_quotes_april_2012/6c7t
Replies from: steven0461↑ comment by steven0461 · 2012-04-17T22:21:35.933Z · LW(p) · GW(p)
comment by RomeoStevens · 2012-04-15T21:49:52.924Z · LW(p) · GW(p)
Happiness research makes me sad.
Replies from: Alicorn↑ comment by Alicorn · 2012-04-16T01:43:24.712Z · LW(p) · GW(p)
Really? How?
Replies from: RomeoStevens↑ comment by RomeoStevens · 2012-04-16T03:39:34.734Z · LW(p) · GW(p)
Humans pine for excess leisure but revealed preference shows that they find excess leisure stressful. People go stir crazy after 2-3 months. I can't say I wouldn't eventually find leisure boring, but I was unemployed for 8 months a couple years ago and it was unequivocally the greatest time in my life. The only lasting negative thoughts I had during that time were thoughts related to it ending. Don't get me wrong, I don't think I'm some wonderfully atypical snowflake, I suspect that many creative/intellectual types would love carte blanche to pursue random projects. But this proportion of the general populace is far smaller than the portion who profess to want it.
Replies from: army1987, Hul-Gil, Apprentice↑ comment by A1987dM (army1987) · 2012-04-20T00:16:52.555Z · LW(p) · GW(p)
I was unemployed for 8 months a couple years ago and it was unequivocally the greatest time in my life.
I guess you somehow still had enough money to fulfil the couple bottom layers of Maslow's hierarchy of needs without much trouble, didn't you?
Replies from: Swimmer963, RomeoStevens↑ comment by Swimmer963 (Miranda Dixon-Luinenburg) (Swimmer963) · 2012-04-20T03:52:09.613Z · LW(p) · GW(p)
Wouldn't most people have enough savings to last 8 months? I'm still in university and I have enough savings to live at my current standard (~$1000/month expenses not including tuition) to live for...hmm, almost 2 years if I'm not in school and paying tuition during that time.
Then again, I guess lifestyle expenses rise along with income after most people graduate, and they might rise faster.
Replies from: thomblake, army1987↑ comment by thomblake · 2012-04-20T16:15:17.342Z · LW(p) · GW(p)
I was under the impression most people in America are in massive debt and have very little savings.
Replies from: Nornagest, Swimmer963↑ comment by Nornagest · 2012-04-20T19:12:00.010Z · LW(p) · GW(p)
I've heard the same, but I'm kind of skeptical -- I haven't actually researched it, but the factoid usually seems to come up when someone's trying to push a narrative, which tends to be a warning sign.
In particular, if mortgages and automotive debt are being counted, then most adults before retirement age might look pretty indebted on paper without that necessarily destroying their medium-term ability to stay solvent. On the other hand, standard financial advice seems to be to maintain six to twelve months' worth of savings, which suggests to me that most people don't.
↑ comment by Swimmer963 (Miranda Dixon-Luinenburg) (Swimmer963) · 2012-04-20T18:53:04.657Z · LW(p) · GW(p)
WHYYYYY??????
Replies from: thomblake, Alicorn, None↑ comment by thomblake · 2012-04-20T20:08:01.944Z · LW(p) · GW(p)
Personally, because of student loans, mortgage (which doesn't really count), and trying to keep up an extravagant standard of living during lean years, justified in part by expectation of making insane amounts of money in the future.
At this point, I have no savings because I'm in debt. I don't have any expectation that I won't be able to come up with however much money I might have saved in the case of an emergency, so the best use of my excess now is to pay off the debt, since interest rates are not in the favor of savings.
↑ comment by Alicorn · 2012-04-20T19:04:28.501Z · LW(p) · GW(p)
Because credit card companies are financially disincentivized to send cards with instructions reading "How To Use Your Credit Card: Borrow our money for free by purchasing things you can afford and paying down your full balance on time, every time, leaving us to profit solely from merchant fees."
Among other causes.
Replies from: TimS↑ comment by TimS · 2012-04-20T19:14:32.806Z · LW(p) · GW(p)
We get to empirically test this assertion, because the new credit card regulations of the last few years have much more detail about the benefits of paying in full, on time.
Replies from: Alicorn↑ comment by Alicorn · 2012-04-20T19:16:29.207Z · LW(p) · GW(p)
If they're long, complicated, and/or in fine print, I don't think that's a test of my assertion.
Replies from: TimS↑ comment by TimS · 2012-04-20T19:20:55.859Z · LW(p) · GW(p)
The first page of the credit card bill now says how much it will cost in interest if you pay only the minimum, or only pay the minimum amount necessary to eventually pay off the debt (along with when that pay off would occur).
It's fairly transparent. Which isn't to say that it overcomes (or attempts to overcome) cognitive biases people have about the relative size of different numbers. But it isn't hiding the ball.
Replies from: Alicorn↑ comment by A1987dM (army1987) · 2012-04-20T13:40:57.935Z · LW(p) · GW(p)
I'd like to remind everyone here that “most people” make less than $851 a year.
Replies from: Swimmer963↑ comment by Swimmer963 (Miranda Dixon-Luinenburg) (Swimmer963) · 2012-04-20T15:58:13.842Z · LW(p) · GW(p)
Excellent point. Funny how brains tend to automatically edit that out, and claim "well, isn't it obvious I was talking about North America/Europe."
Replies from: army1987↑ comment by A1987dM (army1987) · 2012-04-20T19:31:02.801Z · LW(p) · GW(p)
(I'm not completely sure most people -- or even most unemployed adults -- in North America/Europe have enough savings to last 8 months, either.)
↑ comment by RomeoStevens · 2012-04-20T03:12:58.792Z · LW(p) · GW(p)
A maslow interpretation of my behavior would indicate that I respond extremely poorly to a lack of fulfillment of the second level (much more so than the average person). ANY reminder or actions I need to take in order to maintain my current standard of living angers and depresses me. Having 8 months worth of living expenses in the bank gave me a temporary fulfillment of level 2 which was the main cause of my happiness.
↑ comment by Hul-Gil · 2012-04-17T16:38:51.993Z · LW(p) · GW(p)
I have experienced the same thing. I have apparently endless capacity for leisure, possibly because I have an endless number of interests and hobbies to pursue then drop then pick back up. I've never understood people who don't want this kind of life; do they really exist? Can people get bored with leisure?
Replies from: handoflixue, army1987, thomblake, TheOtherDave↑ comment by handoflixue · 2012-04-19T22:39:59.027Z · LW(p) · GW(p)
Can people get bored with leisure?
I'd suspect most people feel both stress from unemployment, and guilt when they are dependent on someone else (or possibly fear of losing this support). I can't really imagine a lot of situations where a person has months to themselves without triggering one of those two, so I'd expect most people aren't very good at evaluating the situation to begin with...
Replies from: None, Nornagest↑ comment by [deleted] · 2012-05-01T05:36:05.849Z · LW(p) · GW(p)
I'd suspect most people feel both stress from unemployment
Mmm. Possibly, but remember that "unemployment" has a fairly arbitrary definition in most cases -- it measures the number of "potential workers" (as in members of the "labour force", which is tough to pin down exactly) who've looked for work within a given time period (usually about four weeks) but haven't been able to find it. It doesn't capture: homemakers, full-time students, incarcerated people, disabled folks who want to work within their abilities but can't find a job, people who've become discouraged from looking for work, people who prefer not to, the self-employed, involuntary retirees, the underemployed, stay-at-home parents, children, elderly folks, most disabled people, and independent farmers. It's possible to be neither "employed" nor "unemployed" by this measure.
My point is, the stress probably isn't from lack-of-employment itself; that's probably a proximate cause, a triggering event that's playing on something else, like simple desperation.
guilt when they are dependent on someone else
That's a matter of culture, I daresay. The Protestant Work Ethic and the self-supporting individual memes are not generalizable to humanity the world over.
Which isn't to say it isn't a common reaction. Just that, as my ultimate point here goes, you should probably not conflate "an inability to meet one's own survival and psychological security needs that's recognizable within one's mental framework" with "leisure." I have lots of free time, in the sense that I'm unemployed and not carrying many obligations day-to-day, but it's hardly all leisure time, and there are things that need to be done in terms of practical upkeep even if that doesn't look like trading labor for biosurvival tickets.
Replies from: handoflixue↑ comment by handoflixue · 2012-05-01T19:30:17.316Z · LW(p) · GW(p)
That sort of reinforces my point - simply "not having a job" doesn't equate to an actual increase in leisure
("Humans pine for excess leisure but revealed preference shows that they find excess leisure stressful" and "I can't say I wouldn't eventually find leisure boring, but I was unemployed for 8 months a couple years ago and it was unequivocally the greatest time in my life. ")
Basically, I'm questioning whether the people studied actually had excess leisure, or just happened to meet certain standards like "not employed full-time in a standard corporation."
Replies from: None↑ comment by Nornagest · 2012-04-19T23:30:33.742Z · LW(p) · GW(p)
I can't really imagine a lot of situations where a person has months to themselves without triggering one of those two...
Retirement, among people with retirement savings and no major health issues yet? I'm sure that's been studied. There's also a number of professions where hiatuses of a couple months at a time are normal -- teaching comes to mind, as do the more lucrative forms of seasonal employment.
Replies from: NancyLebovitz↑ comment by NancyLebovitz · 2012-04-24T08:12:55.914Z · LW(p) · GW(p)
There are also people with inherited money.
There's a category I call the petty rich. They have enough money that they don't need to work, so long as they maintain a middle class or lower lifestyle. I'm not sure how many there are, but I've met a few. I've never seen them discussed or studied-- they aren't exactly conspicuous.
↑ comment by A1987dM (army1987) · 2012-04-20T00:10:15.327Z · LW(p) · GW(p)
Can people get bored with leisure?
I guess some people can and other people can't, where by some I mean ‘a fraction most likely to be more than 5% and less than 95%’.
(As for me, if I have nothing to do for a while I tend to just waste most of my time sleeping or aimlessly browsing the Web and similar addictive-but-not-so-fulfilling stuff, whereas if I'm very busy I spend what little spare time I have on actually fulfilling hobbies and socialising. So I do get bored with leisure, but that's just a result of akrasia and I guess if the next time I get a few spare months I beeminded (say) reading books/watching films/listening to albums/doing things I've always wanted to read/watch/listen/do but never got around to reading/watching/listening/doing, I wouldn't.)
ETA: This guy did get bored with leisure, apparently.
↑ comment by thomblake · 2012-04-17T19:05:09.215Z · LW(p) · GW(p)
Yeah, I find that very confusing too. But then, if pursuing random projects is in "leisure", then I don't really see the distinction between that and "not leisure". Maybe some people just sit around and watch paint dry, given the chance?
Replies from: Hul-Gil↑ comment by TheOtherDave · 2012-04-17T18:39:20.572Z · LW(p) · GW(p)
Yes.
↑ comment by Apprentice · 2012-04-16T12:28:31.120Z · LW(p) · GW(p)
carte blanche to pursue random projects
Define A as "the stuff I would spend my time doing if I got tenure". Define B as "the stuff I would spend my time doing if I became unemployed."
I've been wondering how close A and B are to being identical.
Replies from: Viliam_Bur↑ comment by Viliam_Bur · 2012-04-16T14:23:16.832Z · LW(p) · GW(p)
If you are unemployed, you are running out of money, and you know the time is running out (unless you manage to make something that brings a lot of money soon).
This anxiety can make a huge difference in how you will spent the time. Even if you made the same plans, I would expect more procrastination in situation B.
comment by NancyLebovitz · 2012-04-24T08:50:06.743Z · LW(p) · GW(p)
I think it would be excellent if people who try out any of these suggestions post the results.
Replies from: wedrifid↑ comment by wedrifid · 2012-04-24T09:25:26.925Z · LW(p) · GW(p)
I think it would be excellent if people who try out any of these suggestions post the results.
Even if for no other reason than such examples being powerful motivating influences!
Replies from: NancyLebovitz↑ comment by NancyLebovitz · 2012-04-24T14:22:54.071Z · LW(p) · GW(p)
I need to update towards optimism-- I was thinking about the possibility that the studies were wrong. Admittedly, a lot of them may be-- I don't trust studies about people where there's a lot of extrapolation from a simulated situation-- but the idea that there might be good news didn't even cross my mind.
comment by falenas108 · 2012-04-16T00:30:30.913Z · LW(p) · GW(p)
Excellent article! The only problem I had was that almost every article cited in the spending on others section was written by one group, it would be nice to see other supporters, if they exist.
comment by [deleted] · 2012-04-24T06:02:58.107Z · LW(p) · GW(p)
This makes Robin Hanson's depiction of future brain emulation societies pretty bleak if the basic happiness structure of human minds isn't changed drastically. In his prediction, emulations (ems) will mostly live at near subsistence level and will have to work almost solely on heteronomous goals given by a manager that can probably compel you to provide extreme degrees of cognitive transparency.
Even in modern Western society, there's a big problem with heteronomous goals. I think this is one area where self-hacking is extremely important. I'm planning to write a post one of these days about how I self-hacked and went from absolutely hating writing software to a point where I routinely get in the "flow" while writing code and feel happy. Even still, I would describe myself as 'hating' software, but if a manager assigns tasks that require writing lots of software, it doesn't negatively affect me any more.
Given how much happiness depends on autonomous goals, our society that compels us to do heteronomous tasks that we typically don't care about and don't enjoy and would not do other than that we need the money seems quite backwards. And yet few would agree that life would be better in alternatively organized societies (especially when pressed to consider all the daily innovations we take for granted, akin to Don Boudreaux's "Cleaned By Capitalism" posts).
This is very puzzling. It explains why so many people are banging down the door to be underpaid/overworked grad students. The dream of almost all goals being autonomous (tenured research faculty at prestigious college) is almost lifestyle masturbation compared to what most people experience.
comment by b1shop · 2012-04-15T12:40:49.344Z · LW(p) · GW(p)
Gut reaction: Working out has an externality. Muscle tone applies a cost on others who must devote more of their time (which can be measured in dollars, by the way) toward the positional signalling game of fitness. Does this mean we should avoid conspicuous health?
Second reaction: I don't like this advice. Maybe I value other goals higher than happiness.
Replies from: gwern, Good_Burning_Plastic, Klevador, army1987↑ comment by gwern · 2012-04-15T15:01:40.580Z · LW(p) · GW(p)
Does muscle tone not contribute to genuine health and longevity? That's a positive externality being generated right there.
Replies from: b1shop↑ comment by b1shop · 2012-04-15T15:31:06.226Z · LW(p) · GW(p)
Doesn't buying a nice house contribute to genuine peace and stability while forcing a potential spendthrift to start saving? That's an internalized benefit.
Just because something has benefits doesn't mean it has externalized costs.
Replies from: gwern↑ comment by gwern · 2012-04-15T16:58:12.405Z · LW(p) · GW(p)
Doesn't buying a nice house contribute to genuine peace and stability while forcing a potential spendthrift to start saving?
Or does it contribute to speculative bubbles, and increase unemployment by forcing 'stability' (inflexibility & stasis)?
Replies from: b1shop"Just as the blowing winds preserve the sea from the foulness that would be the result of a prolonged calm, so also corruption in nations would be the result of prolonged - let alone perpetual - peace."
↑ comment by b1shop · 2012-04-15T17:35:58.051Z · LW(p) · GW(p)
For the record, I agree that home ownership isn't worth it for most prices. Bad example on my part.
I stand by my original point. Just because working out has benefits doesn't mean it's not without negative externalities.
Replies from: gwern↑ comment by gwern · 2012-04-15T17:59:17.989Z · LW(p) · GW(p)
Just because working out has benefits doesn't mean it's not without negative externalities.
Sure, but this is something that could be said of everything - everything has consequences which one has not foreseen. That's the first law of ecology.
Unless you have specific reason to bring that up, or good evidence that the obvious benefits are outweighed by subtler negative externalities that others have noticed, or something, why are we discussing it?
Replies from: b1shop↑ comment by b1shop · 2012-04-15T21:35:04.005Z · LW(p) · GW(p)
Because the linked-to study simply says "conspicuous consumption has negative externalities" and the conclusion given is "Avoid Conspicuous Consumption." I call foul.
Replies from: Klevador↑ comment by Klevador · 2012-04-16T07:10:09.476Z · LW(p) · GW(p)
‘positional goods’ which, by definition, cannot be augmented, because they rely solely on not being available to others.
-
... the production of positional goods in the form of luxuries, such as exceedingly expensive watches or yachts, is a waste of productive resources, as overall happiness is thereby decreased rather than increased.
^ This is specific to wealth and cannot (necessarily) be said of other forms of status, such as fitness.
↑ comment by Good_Burning_Plastic · 2016-02-10T14:04:50.562Z · LW(p) · GW(p)
That's a pecuniary externality. People of your same gender will find it harder to compete, but people of your preferred gender will have more attractive potential mates available.
↑ comment by Klevador · 2012-04-15T12:57:26.813Z · LW(p) · GW(p)
The term "conspicuous consumption" is commonly applied to displays of (financial) wealth; the recommendation to avoid conspicuous consumption does not imply that you should avoid all forms of conspicuous superiority. I'm not sure that fitness-as-status is so closely analogous to wealth-as-status.
Replies from: hvass, b1shop, NancyLebovitz↑ comment by hvass · 2012-04-15T20:29:54.035Z · LW(p) · GW(p)
For heterosexual men, one reason to exhibit conspicuous consumption is the dating game. :-) And for everyone else, I think the Halo Effect is quite a good reason as well especially for clothes. But focus on experiences of course, just don't go into a complete extreme.
↑ comment by b1shop · 2012-04-15T13:53:50.890Z · LW(p) · GW(p)
It's the same reasoning as the "avoid conspicuous consumption" lemma, and it could also be applied to education-as-status, lawncare-as-status, fashion-as-status, art-as-status or karma-as-status. Maybe the lesson could be rewritten as "Conspicuous Consumption has Costs on Others"? That seems like an unbiased reading of that study.
But I'm not even sure if I agree with that. If conspicuous consumption encourages others to become productive members of society out of envy, then it has its societal benefits.
Replies from: Klevador↑ comment by Klevador · 2012-04-16T06:55:39.366Z · LW(p) · GW(p)
You seem to be saying that the rules of the game of wealth-as-status are the same as those for fitness-as-status, to take one of your examples. But this is not at all clear to me. Wealth can be stolen and given away. Wealth can be amassed. Fitness is accessible to most people in a way that wealth is not.
That seems like an unbiased reading of that study.
I'd say that it is an overgeneralization of the findings.
Replies from: Jayson_Virissimo↑ comment by Jayson_Virissimo · 2012-04-17T09:29:18.054Z · LW(p) · GW(p)
Fitness is accessible to most people in a way that wealth is not.
In what way is fitness accessible to most people but wealth is not?
Replies from: army1987↑ comment by A1987dM (army1987) · 2012-04-17T10:40:58.999Z · LW(p) · GW(p)
Make that "to most people in the developed world", then. If I want more fitness, I just have to exercise more and eat better, which the majority of people in the developed world could afford with little trouble if they wanted to. (Programs like the 5BX take less than half an hour a day -- personally I use Goodbye Couch.) If I want more wealth (and here we're talking about an amount of wealth that can buy "exceedingly expensive watches or yachts", not just a couple hundred more dollars per months) there's very little I can do to reliably achieve that.
↑ comment by NancyLebovitz · 2012-04-15T16:24:46.158Z · LW(p) · GW(p)
The interesting question might be whether the usual way of signalling health (muscle bulk and low fat-- more bulk for men than women) is as closely connected to actual health (longevity, energy, enjoyment of life, disease resistance, fun, probably more....) as the culture assumes. What's a optimal pursuit of looking healthy?
Replies from: wedrifid↑ comment by wedrifid · 2012-04-15T18:04:25.356Z · LW(p) · GW(p)
The interesting question might be whether the usual way of signalling health (muscle bulk and low fat-- more bulk for men than women) is as closely connected to actual health (longevity, energy, enjoyment of life, disease resistance, fun, probably more....) as the culture assumes.
As far as I am aware the 'low fat' signal is a cultural idiosyncrasy. All else being equal it's a signal of somewhat less disease resistance.
Replies from: army1987↑ comment by A1987dM (army1987) · 2012-04-17T10:25:45.471Z · LW(p) · GW(p)
Why are people assuming that the relationship between fat and health must be monotonic?
Replies from: wedrifid↑ comment by wedrifid · 2012-04-17T12:11:32.488Z · LW(p) · GW(p)
Why are people assuming that the relationship between fat and health must be monotonic?
They aren't. That would be crazy.
Replies from: army1987↑ comment by A1987dM (army1987) · 2012-04-17T15:16:19.979Z · LW(p) · GW(p)
So, from the fact that underweight people are less healthy than neither-underweight-nor-overweight people it doesn't follow that overweight people are also healthier than neither-underweight-nor-overweight people, and hence that there's no good reason (other than signalling) for people to not want to be overweight, does it? (Or am I misunderstanding what the whole issue is about?)
↑ comment by A1987dM (army1987) · 2012-04-17T10:32:45.693Z · LW(p) · GW(p)
Muscle tone applies a cost on others who must devote more of their time (which can be measured in dollars, by the way) toward the positional signalling game of fitness. Does this mean we should avoid conspicuous health?
Let's work this out TDT-style: if the right answer to the question "should you exercise" is "no (because that would make others jealous unless they exercise too, because then they wouldn't look as good as you)" you get a world with people who don't exercise. If it is "yes (because then you'd look better)" you get a world with people who do exercise. I'd pretty much prefer the latter world. IOW, I'm not sure that this game is purely positional (i.e. zero-sum).
Replies from: wedrifid↑ comment by wedrifid · 2012-04-17T14:06:19.964Z · LW(p) · GW(p)
Let's work this out TDT-style: if the right answer to the question "should you exercise" is "no (because that would make others jealous unless they exercise too, because then they wouldn't look as good as you)" you get a world with people who don't exercise.
I hate seeing TDT agents described as thinking like that. Because they just don't.
comment by drethelin · 2012-04-15T06:38:58.185Z · LW(p) · GW(p)
cannot upvote this enough
Replies from: MichaelVassar↑ comment by MichaelVassar · 2012-04-17T05:03:20.246Z · LW(p) · GW(p)
Why is a request to upvote being upvoted?
Replies from: thomblake, drethelin, army1987↑ comment by thomblake · 2012-04-17T12:20:07.565Z · LW(p) · GW(p)
It's not a request to upvote - it's a statement of approval. And as per Why our kind can't cooperate, vacuous statements of approval or agreement are upvote-worthy, if only because of their rarity.
Replies from: John_Maxwell_IV↑ comment by John_Maxwell (John_Maxwell_IV) · 2012-04-20T05:10:49.613Z · LW(p) · GW(p)
An even better idea would be to send the author a private message in appreciation; that wouldn't decrease the signal-to-noise ratio but would have the same positive reinforcement effect.
↑ comment by drethelin · 2012-04-17T05:07:26.990Z · LW(p) · GW(p)
If you think this is bad you should see my comment on the hpmor thread that got upvoted 12 points for just agreeing with the parent
Replies from: army1987↑ comment by A1987dM (army1987) · 2012-04-17T10:55:02.271Z · LW(p) · GW(p)
Yeah, http://lesswrong.com/r/discussion/topcomments/ is always full of comments in HPMOR discussions. (As of now, only one of this week's top ten comments is not in a HPMOR thread.) It bothers the hell out of me.
Replies from: DanPeverley, Dias↑ comment by DanPeverley · 2012-04-17T21:42:13.653Z · LW(p) · GW(p)
Everyone goes into those threads primed to be friendly to the other people, because they are all members of the same fan-fiction reading in-group. There is also a shift from "on a rationality site" mode to "talking about media" mode, where rigor in voting rationale tends to become somewhat more lax. I don't mind, but I'm part of the in-group so that's to be expected.
↑ comment by Dias · 2012-04-19T08:02:05.296Z · LW(p) · GW(p)
On the plus side, if that thread has a lot of new people drawn by HPMOR, so we may not want to subject them to such stringent standards.
On the other hand, I think we upvote (orrather, don't downvote enough) in the rest of LW too much anyway.
↑ comment by A1987dM (army1987) · 2012-04-17T10:41:42.165Z · LW(p) · GW(p)
Because someone wants to see more comments like that?
comment by MarkusRamikin · 2012-04-21T11:25:29.036Z · LW(p) · GW(p)
That's well done.
Can you make one about taking over the world?
Replies from: Paulovskcomment by habryka (habryka4) · 2019-04-24T20:22:15.740Z · LW(p) · GW(p)
Mode note: Fixed the old semi-broken HTML formatting for this post. Old formatting is still available as a revision.
comment by Micaiah_Chang · 2012-04-22T19:13:39.002Z · LW(p) · GW(p)
Hm, I don't see anything in there at this moment; and I'm not confident enough to say that I know everything in the article but...
Is there any research on how entertainment *types affects happiness levels? I don't mean genres necessarily, but let's say, low cognitive load works like Bond movies, summer action flicks and slapstick comedies versus 'artsy' high cognitive load works like Schindler's list, Shakespeare plays and hard scifi.
So what I have is two apparently conflicting pieces of information. I know that people like to put off the latter for the former. Suggesting that people feel as if the EV from the artsy works is lower (because of prep time needed to get into the right emotional state, thinking required during the work, a more abstract impression of its qualities from reviews rather than colleagues).
You're also supposed to enjoy artsy stuff more, and it happens to pattern match to some of the happiness advice here: The salient feature of artsy works is that it's easy to reflect on them, they tend to be novel, "sad" works brings your "haves" into sharp relief, the preparation and delay of the experience...
Actually, could it be that artsy works are viewed as artsy because of the memeplex we set up around them rather than any inherent, mysterious quality factor surrounding them? Hm. If this were true, it would mean that if we treated pop culture like high culture, we'd get the same amount of high utility from more sources.
Of course, I could be overthinking this; it's mere akrasia favoring pop culture, high culture is high culture simply because it's 'objectively the best' and all the pattern matching I did earlier is proof of quality.
comment by pnrjulius · 2012-04-17T02:19:15.265Z · LW(p) · GW(p)
This needs to be broken up into smaller, more digestible sub-articles. It's too much to take in all at once.
Replies from: Klevador↑ comment by Klevador · 2012-04-17T05:46:22.166Z · LW(p) · GW(p)
I don't know... you don't have to take it in all at once. You can read just one section at a time, after all. Each section has a link to it in the summary. What is the added advantage in splitting it up?
Replies from: Randaly, John_Maxwell_IV↑ comment by John_Maxwell (John_Maxwell_IV) · 2012-04-20T05:13:51.215Z · LW(p) · GW(p)
Let's think in consequentialist terms here. You obviously put forth a lot of useful effort, thanks for that! But realistically, it seems plausible that the material is not being presented in a way that is maximally accessible, and your post could potentially be even more awesome than it already is!
I'm not suggesting you change anything at this point, just pointing stuff out.
Replies from: Klevador↑ comment by Klevador · 2012-04-20T09:48:45.492Z · LW(p) · GW(p)
^ But, that can be said of too many things. I don't find it meaningful.
e.g. 'It's plausible that Harry Potter has not been written in the best possible way.'
Of course it's plausible, but the consideration of its plausibility does not contribute to making better-informed decisions. It contributes no useful information!
Replies from: John_Maxwell_IV↑ comment by John_Maxwell (John_Maxwell_IV) · 2012-04-20T23:28:32.119Z · LW(p) · GW(p)
Right. The real question is how much the post could improve given an hour's effort; in other words, how much improvement could you buy for an hour of labor. And I'm suggesting that you could get a pretty good deal.
comment by torekp · 2012-04-16T19:28:49.852Z · LW(p) · GW(p)
How do Philippe et al distinguish "obsessive" from "harmonious" passion?
Replies from: Klevador↑ comment by Klevador · 2012-04-17T05:41:42.992Z · LW(p) · GW(p)
Good catch! Here is their definition (will update the main post later). Bolding mine:
Vallerand and his colleagues [...] have recently proposed a Dualistic Model of Passion in which passion is defined as a strong inclina-tion or desire toward a self-defining activity that one likes (or even loves), finds important (high valuation), and in which one invests time and energy.
The Dualistic Model of Passion further proposes that there exist two types of passion. The first type of passion is harmonious passion. A harmonious passion produces a strong desire to engage in the activity which remains under the person’s control. This type of passion results from an autonomous internalisation of the activity into the person’s identity (Deci & Ryan, 2000; Vallerand et al., 2003). An autonomous internalisation occurs when individuals have freely accepted the activity as important for them without any contingencies attached to it (Sheldon, 2002; Vallerand, 1997). In such a case, the activity occupies a significant but not overpowering space in the person’s identity and is in harmony with other aspects of the person’s life. An example of such a type of passion would be that with harmonious passion the person strongly loves and values basketball. However, this person also keeps control over the activity and can freely decide when to engage or not in basketball and when to stop engagement. Basketball would then be engaged in because of the pleasure that is drawn from the activity and not from other extrinsic sources (e.g. being popular because of basketball) and leads to a task-focus involvement that is conducive to positive outcomes (e.g. positive affect, flow, concentration).
The second type of passion identified by Vallerand and colleagues (2003) is obsessive passion. This type of passion entails the same strong desire to engage in the activity, as in harmonious passion. However, this desire of engagement is not under the person’s control. Rather, it is as if the activity controlled the person. Obsessive passion results from a controlled internalisation of the activity into one’s identity (Vallerand et al., 2003). Such an internalisation originates from intra and/or interpersonal pressure because certain contingencies are attached to the activity such as feelings of social acceptance, self-esteem, or performance. Thus, although individuals like the activity, they cannot help but engage in it due to a lack of control over these internal contingencies that come to control the person. It is proposed that individuals with an obsessive passion come to develop ego-invested structures (Hodgins & Knee, 2002) and eventually display rigid and conflicted forms of task engagement that preclude the experience of volition in activity engagement. An example of such a type of passion could be a person who strongly loves and values basketball, but because this activity fulfills a strong need for approval or performance which boosts momentarily one’s self- esteem, this person cannot help but engage in basketball, including at times when the activity should not be engaged in or should be stopped. This type of passion should not be confused with the concept of addiction for an activity. An addiction for a daily activity such as sports, gardening, or playing of a musical instrument usually constitutes a very rare pathology. In addition, addictions are often used to describe substance abuse, such as smoking, alcohol drinking, or drug abuse, which can hardly be conceptualised as an activity (gambling might be an exception). Finally, an important distinction between obsessive passion and addiction is that the addict person does not perceive his/her addictive activity as enjoyable anymore, while loving and valuing the activity are core criteria of obsessive passion. Addic- tive gamblers for instance do not like gambling anymore; they want to stop gambling and often seek therapies by themselves or self-exclude themselves from casinos.
comment by Desrtopa · 2012-04-15T13:39:50.881Z · LW(p) · GW(p)
Spend on others, especially people you are close to.
This one sounds dubious to me if you happen to be rich. I always thought that if I were rich, I would make a public precommitment only to give away money to worthy charities, so as to avoid worry that anyone trying to get close to me was really trying to get close to the money. Maybe it doesn't work out that way?
Replies from: TheOtherDave↑ comment by TheOtherDave · 2012-04-15T16:13:20.756Z · LW(p) · GW(p)
It seems simpler to just include my money in what I identify with. I mean, it doesn't bug me that people trying to get close to me might really be trying to get close to my sense of humor, or my appearance, or my kind demeanor, or various other attributes of mine. Why make an exception for money?
But the more traditional solution to this "problem" is to make friends among people with roughly the same level of wealth.
Replies from: Desrtopa↑ comment by Desrtopa · 2012-05-16T13:51:25.354Z · LW(p) · GW(p)
I wouldn't mind letting people who get close to me partake of my sense of humor, attractiveness, or good nature, because these aren't resources that are diminished by being shared among others. But if people want to get close to me in order to induce me to distribute my expendable resources among them, I'm going to feel resentful, because anything I spend on them is an opportunity cost, and they're faking signals that would qualify them for special consideration in my utility function. If they weren't pretending to enjoy my company for any other reason, and were open about just wanting to be where the money was, I would feel comfortable rebuffing them.
(I somehow failed to notice this response until just now.)
Replies from: TheOtherDave↑ comment by TheOtherDave · 2012-05-16T14:25:10.373Z · LW(p) · GW(p)
(nods) Yeah, I resonate emotionally with this, but on consideration I don't really endorse it.
Even things like humor and kindness are functions of attention, which is also a limited resource, and attractiveness plays a complex role in social-status economies. If someone were open about just pretending to be my friend in order to get access to those resources, it seems I ought to feel just as comfortable rebuffing them, although I expect that in practice I would mostly be confused, since I do not have as clear an understanding of social resources as I do of money.
Replies from: Desrtopa↑ comment by Desrtopa · 2012-05-16T15:59:44.808Z · LW(p) · GW(p)
Having friends at all costs attention, but I don't invest extra attentional resources into being funny or kind to people around me. If anything, it takes less energy for me to be friendly and funny around people I'm comfortable with than it does for me to be distant or awkward around people I'm uncomfortable with. If I'm going to invest my attention into spending time with people at all, I'd rather they be positive interactions.
Replies from: TheOtherDave↑ comment by TheOtherDave · 2012-05-16T16:46:20.779Z · LW(p) · GW(p)
Interesting. It definitely does consume extra resources for me. I became most vividly aware of this after my stroke, when attentional resources were very scarce, and I often ran out of them in mid-interaction, and even basic social interaction became incredibly exhausting; my irritation about this very much resembled the feeling of having all my employed friends insisting on going out to dinner when I was unemployed and poor. (I don't care about it so much anymore, in either area, because I'm now running a large surplus of both money and attention.)
comment by [deleted] · 2016-02-19T05:39:08.612Z · LW(p) · GW(p)
These are some key takeaways (stolen without permission from elsewhere...)
Appreciate
- Be grateful and count your blessings (literally). Recycle happiness by reminiscing about good experiences.
- Think of counterfactuals. (“If I didn’t have this positive thing, what do I lose?”)
- Breathe deeply. Expand your time — by slowing down.
- Actively want to be happier. Motivation and investment matter.
- Stay in the present.
- Be passionate, but don’t obsess.
Care
- Socialize with close others.
- Associate with happy people.
- Give the people around you opportunities to be generous. Ask them for favors.
- Be actively kind (and occasionally reminisce about your recent acts of kindness).
Plan
- Go for ‘approach’ goals instead of ‘avoid’ goals.
- Do work that you enjoy doing. Flow.
- Keep your goals intrinsic.
- Conclude negative experiences as soon as possible.
- Make a point of avoiding experiences that make you feel bad.
Give
- Don’t think too much about money. It will impair your savoring ability. It's also bad for your family life.
- Be time-aware, but don’t think of time in terms of money.
- Prefer experiential purchases; avoid materialistic goals.
- Don’t do ‘comparison shopping.’ And don’t place much stock in the happiness potential of any one positive change.
- Follow the herd. “The best way to predict how much we will enjoy an experience is to see how much someone else enjoyed it.”
- Savor anticipation. Delay consumption. Actively anticipate good experiences.
comment by Logos01 · 2012-04-24T06:39:21.860Z · LW(p) · GW(p)
Alright... after reading through much of this, a certain line struck me over and over again.
Actively want to be happier. Motivation and investment matter.
I have only one question.
Why?
(To clarify: I mean: Why be happy? Why want to be happy? How is it useful? What 'good' is happiness?)
Replies from: Richard_Kennaway, Raemon, Zaine, fubarobfusco↑ comment by Richard_Kennaway · 2012-04-24T06:53:58.601Z · LW(p) · GW(p)
I agree with Will Newsome's comment, especially the second paragraph.
Looking for "happiness" as something distinct from and on top of living the life you truly want is like going to London and looking for "London". A signpost pointing to "London" is only useful when you are far from it.
↑ comment by Raemon · 2012-04-24T19:28:19.944Z · LW(p) · GW(p)
It's some people's terminal value. It's okay if it's not yours.
Is there a more complicated reason why you feel "fulfilling your potential to impact the world" is important?
Replies from: Logos01↑ comment by Logos01 · 2012-04-24T23:15:27.547Z · LW(p) · GW(p)
Not fulfilling the potential itself, but rather the capacity to do so, (which can only properly be measured by the actualization / acting-upon-of said capacity). As to why -- well, fundamentally it's the notion that maximized instrumentality is the maximally optimal instrumental state. From there the question becomes; "is maximized instrumentality useful?"
That is a "self-proving" terminal value. One need only ask the question to see that it implies its answer. "Is being useful useful?" Well... yes. Whatever it is you want to do or achieve is transparent / irrelevant to this.
Being useful is useful. The "use" of being useful is that it's useful.
These are essentially tautological statements.
So when I ask, "what's the use of being happy" -- saying "It makes you happy" is true (tautologically) but not an expression of utility, whereas having utility is useful because it's useful is also tautologically true but is an expression of utility.
Replies from: tog↑ comment by Zaine · 2012-04-25T03:52:05.948Z · LW(p) · GW(p)
I've read your other responses, and while I don't think my experience will assist you in an attempt to feel the emotion, it may assist in your ability to understand the emotion's desirability.
I find myself more productive when I'm happy; my mind has less cluttered thoughts, due to less anxiety and cognitive duress (I can only best describe this as a state when my subconscious works overtime on thoughts I'm only barely conscious of, and each time I try to deeply contemplate a new thought, somewhere along the halfway point it's unwillingly relegated to my subconscious as something I'm anxious over pops to the top of my mind).
I also notice a correlation between times I am unhappy, and a lowering in my self-confidence. Normally my confidence hovers right below what I would consider 'a level of confidence conducive to hubris', and when happy, it can tend to spill over into this danger zone. When unhappy, my confidence becomes akin to the normative level of confidence I've observed most people whom I've encountered to likely possess. This diminishing of confidence too lessens my productivity, and to reestablish my normative confidence level, I must then end my unhappiness.
Thus, for me, over-abundant happiness can be dangerous, but wading just above the happiness threshold gives me clarity of mind and purposeful focus. Hope this helped elucidate happiness's utility for you.
Cheers!
↑ comment by Logos01 · 2012-04-25T06:28:48.035Z · LW(p) · GW(p)
I also notice a correlation between times I am unhappy,
One fo the many things I dislike about the English language is that it does not readily acknowledge that "happy" is no excluded middle.
Replies from: Zaine↑ comment by Zaine · 2012-04-25T10:40:23.854Z · LW(p) · GW(p)
I consider my normative state to be just under or around the 'happy' threshold, which I'd consider as between happiness and unhappiness. Happiness essentially equates to a certain chemical balance in the brain, and the same holds true for unhappiness. When the brain releases neurotransmitters equitably, I'd postulate the brain's chemical balance to reflect neutral emotions.
As an aside, I've heard genuinely, innocently laughing releases endorphins just as effectively as exercise; what do you emotively experience when these endorphins release? If you want to hack happiness, exercise or some media you find consistently hilarious might work through pure chemistry.
(Note: I may be mistaken in the neuroscience, though doubt it; I'm working on a piece of paper that declares proficiency in the field.)
↑ comment by adamisom · 2012-04-25T04:11:31.025Z · LW(p) · GW(p)
Might I recommend following Zaine's description with this paragraph from Luke's How To Be Happy:
IgnoreWe all want to be happy, as apparently you don't, but continue with and happiness is useful for other things, too.2 For example, happiness improves physical health,3 improves creativity,4 and even enables you to make better decisions.5 (It's harder to be rational when you're unhappy.6)
EDIT: note that the formatting is off in copy and paste. Comments do not support subscripts. numbers 2-6 refer to notes in the article
↑ comment by fubarobfusco · 2012-04-24T06:57:33.875Z · LW(p) · GW(p)
(To clarify: I mean: Why be happy? Why want to be happy? How is it useful? What 'good' is happiness?)
Might be fun?
Sure beats the alternative?
It's compatible with all the good drugs and keeps you off all the bad ones?
Replies from: Logos01↑ comment by Logos01 · 2012-04-24T07:07:10.244Z · LW(p) · GW(p)
Might be fun?
Okay. So what?
Sure beats the alternative?
Does it? Why? What is the alternative? How is 'happy' better?
It's compatible with all the good drugs and keeps you off all the bad ones?
I can't help but not that this is post hoc ergo propter hoc reasoning.
Let's engage in a bit of an exercise. I am a thirty year old man. I have never in my life experienced happiness. I have no prospects of becoming happy. Everyone I have ever seen who was happy seemed, in many fundamental ways, contemptible to me: they were complacent, they were 'satisfied'; they settled and lacked any driving ambition or devotion to achieving the uttermost limits of what they could achieve or become. They did not utilize the maximum of their potential to impact the world, and instead... seem less.
Explain to me why I should want to be like that. What is useful about this? Why is it good?
I am open to total revision of my worldview. I come to this dialogue with a history that I relate only to reveal my preconceptions; that they might be accounted for.
So to hug the hypothesis: "What's so great about being happy?"
Replies from: Richard_Kennaway, adamisom↑ comment by Richard_Kennaway · 2012-04-24T11:00:14.785Z · LW(p) · GW(p)
Everyone I have ever seen who was happy seemed, in many fundamental ways, contemptible to me
Did these people differ in this respect from people who were not happy? And does the post hoc propter hoc thing apply here also?
ETA: If "happiness" is the state of living the life you truly want, then if your wants are small, "happiness" will be easily achieved, but if your wants are large, not so easily. You will therefore observe of people that on average, the greater their ambition, the less their happiness; the greater their happiness, the less their ambition. It would be an error to read the wrong causality into this correlation, and attempt to achieve happiness "by lopping off our desires, ... like cutting off our feet, when we want shoes." (Jonathan Swift)
"Happiness" is neither to be aimed at nor avoided. Doing what you truly want is to be aimed at, and not avoided.
Replies from: Logos01↑ comment by Logos01 · 2012-04-24T16:03:37.807Z · LW(p) · GW(p)
"Happiness" is neither to be aimed at nor avoided. Doing what you truly want is to be aimed at, and not avoided.
So then you reject altogether the core premise of the article, which also stated; "Actively want to be happier. Motivation and investment matter."
Of course, I can also note that the only way, from my perspective, to guarantee your maximal significance (in terms of material impact upon the world) -- is to always strive for something you don't have; to wish to be more than you are in every possible sense of the word... including the efficacy with which you strive for more.
In other words; to 'condemn' yourself to always be incapable of doing what you "truly want" -- because you will never, ever be good enough at getting better.
Replies from: Richard_Kennaway↑ comment by Richard_Kennaway · 2012-04-24T17:21:56.771Z · LW(p) · GW(p)
What are you doing about it?
Replies from: Logos01↑ comment by Logos01 · 2012-04-24T23:00:10.040Z · LW(p) · GW(p)
That question segfaults in my parser.
Replies from: Richard_Kennaway↑ comment by Richard_Kennaway · 2012-04-24T23:03:20.732Z · LW(p) · GW(p)
I meant, borrowing your words, are you consumed with a driving ambition or devotion to achieving the uttermost limits of what you could achieve or become, utilizing the maximum of your potential to impact the world? Are you always striving for something you don't have; wishing to be more than you are in every possible sense of the word... including the efficacy with which you strive for more?
And if so, what are you doing about it?
Replies from: Logos01↑ comment by Logos01 · 2012-04-24T23:26:03.557Z · LW(p) · GW(p)
I meant, borrowing your words, are you consumed with a driving ambition or devotion to achieving the uttermost limits of what you could achieve or become, utilizing the maximum of your potential to impact the world? Are you always striving for something you don't have; wishing to be more than you are in every possible sense of the word... including the efficacy with which you strive for more?
Not as much as I should be.
And if so, what are you doing about it?
1) Completely overhauling my professional capacity and career-path. In the last two years I've changed tracks to the point where my income has doubled year-over-year from that point, and am set to another 'doubling'.
2) I am systematically seeking out those areas where I am most deficient and am seeking means to bypass, exploit, or otherwise mitigate or account for those deficiencies. I have had setbacks and failures across the board, but I do not allow them to stop me. I have had a total collapse of my professional, personal, social, and romantic lives/livelihoods on more than one occassion, and in each instance I've "dusted myself off and picked back up again" as it were. I'm currently working on how to rebuild my social life (as it is utterly lacking) but I suspect that once my fiscal situation becomes stabilized at the newly higher point I'll have more attentional reserves available to dedicate to this. Another area I am constantly lacking in since my teen years is my physical excellence and dietary habits. I don't have the cognitive/attentional reserves to address the exercise regimen just yet, but that's coming. The diet I also am working on; exposing myself to new foods and food combinations in order to expand my pallatte (as an autist this is an exceptional challenge for me in ways that are non-obvious.)
None of these things are, to be quite frank, particularly pleasant. I typically can't stand people for example; and though I have been told time and again I make an "excellent" host/guest/conversationalist/party-goer... it's physically exhausting to me (this is related to cognitive deficiencies on my part; I am unable to 'filter' out things and must consciously assign attentional levels to all things around me -- try staying perfectly alert in complex settings for, say, an hour or two and you'll get why being around groups of people is exhausting to me.). Despite this I have raised that as a priority on my regimen because being able to cause compliance in people without their perceiving it as duress is useful. This is also why I've been teaching myself how to code; and why I also pay attention to any manner of topics.
I could keep going down the list, but that about summarizes it.
Replies from: Richard_Kennaway, Zaine↑ comment by Richard_Kennaway · 2012-04-25T09:05:33.758Z · LW(p) · GW(p)
Sounds like the right track.
To answer your earlier question:
So then you reject altogether the core premise of the article, which also stated; "Actively want to be happier. Motivation and investment matter."
Pretty much. I'd rather do what I want than pursue fuzzies. The cake is a lie.
↑ comment by Zaine · 2012-04-25T03:57:34.619Z · LW(p) · GW(p)
Have you read Mountains Beyond Mountains by Tracy Kidder? It's a non-fiction book recording the story of Dr. Paul Farmer, a tremendously benevolent epidemiologist that shares your worldview, does all he can to medically assist the poor (specifically, the Haitian poor), and still cannot meet the standards he sets himself. However, Kidder's depictions of Farmer's personality portray him as a happy man. Perhaps the book will be of some help, if you indeed have not yet read it.
Replies from: Logos01↑ comment by Logos01 · 2012-04-25T06:30:39.494Z · LW(p) · GW(p)
However, Kidder's depictions of Farmer's personality portray him as a happy man. Perhaps the book will be of some help, if you indeed have not yet read it.
I'm quite certain that the vast majority of people who ever encountered me in meatspace would make the mistake of thinking that I am a happy person. I laugh, I smile, I go through all of the motions. I am upbeat and concerned with the wellbeing of others. I am patient to a fault, and nigh unto never show any signs of any kind of being foul-mannered or intemperate.
Those who know me when I am ... myself -- know a very different person. They are few.
Replies from: Zaine↑ comment by Zaine · 2012-04-25T10:21:42.051Z · LW(p) · GW(p)
This is still in line with Kidder's depiction of Farmer. In one scene, Farmer has dinner with two close colleagues with whom he's worked a long time. Kidder has been invited by Farmer, but compared to his usual, jovial self, Farmer blows up at one of his colleagues and beleaguers the colleague on how they are not serving the people who need them most (poor people) first. Kidder, shocked at how Farmer so blatantly torments and manipulates his colleague into capitulating to Farmer's wishes, asks the other colleague whether this is normal. She responds, "You think that was bad? What he was doing to Jim was nothing. On a a scale of one to ten, that was about a five."
Regardless, the book both educates and entertains; I recommend at least checking it out.
↑ comment by adamisom · 2012-04-24T17:41:06.214Z · LW(p) · GW(p)
Emotion dressed up as pseudo-intellectualism. How do I know that/ Because the answer is so supremely obvious.
Others - happiness terminal value You - (apparently) maximizing potential terminal value
... What exactly is so baffling? People want to be happy for it's own sake. You can say "cuz it feels good" or whatever, but in the end you're going to be faced with the fact that it's just a terminal value and you're going to have a hard time "explaining" it.
P.S. The specific use of the word contemptible is what tipped me off to the fact that you're not emotionally prepared to ask a good question here.
Replies from: Logos01↑ comment by Logos01 · 2012-04-24T23:04:44.374Z · LW(p) · GW(p)
Emotion dressed up as pseudo-intellectualism. How do I know that/ Because the answer is so supremely obvious.
... Is there maybe some other manner in which I could explain that I was revealing my emotional biases in order to get them out of the way of the dialogue that would be more effective for you?
... What exactly is so baffling? People want to be happy for it's own sake
Why? The position is alien to me.
but in the end you're going to be faced with the fact that it's just a terminal value and you're going to have a hard time "explaining" it.
Handwaving is non-explanation. You might as well say "because magic". I was opening myself up to the dialogue of perhaps exploring mindspace alien to me -- and giving others the opportunity to do so in kind.
P.S. The specific use of the word contemptible is what tipped me off to the fact that you're not emotionally prepared to ask a good question here.
:-|
That's all I got. Maybe someone better suited to the dialogue will come along. Thanks for your time I guess?
Replies from: wedrifid↑ comment by wedrifid · 2012-04-25T02:10:43.739Z · LW(p) · GW(p)
... What exactly is so baffling? People want to be happy for it's own sake
Why?
The only useful answer here seems to be giving a causal explanation for why humans have the preferences that they have. Something to do with the folks who have different preferences not living long enough to get laid a lot. There isn't any reasoning that people need to execute based on more fundamental principles of what to desire. This is just what they happen to do.
The position is alien to me.
It is rather common to you fellow humans.
Replies from: Logos01↑ comment by Logos01 · 2012-04-25T02:52:56.308Z · LW(p) · GW(p)
This is just what they happen to do.
This is nonsensical. Do we always conform to patterns merely because they're the patterns we always adhered to, unquestioningly? The question is being asked now.
If there is no decent answer -- then what justifies this article?
Replies from: adamisom, wedrifid↑ comment by adamisom · 2012-04-25T03:21:00.331Z · LW(p) · GW(p)
(Apologies for my earlier comment. I've been in a negative emotional funk lately, and at least I am more self-aware because of that comment and its response. Anyway---)
I'm a little confused about why you think it's hand-waving or question-begging to call happiness a 'terminal value'. Here's why.
Your utility function is just a representation of what you want to increase. So if happiness is what you want to increase, it ought to be represented (heavily) in your utility function, whatever that is. As far as I know, "utility" is a (philosophical) explication - a more precise and formalized way of talking about something. This is a concept I learned from some metalogic: logic is an "explication", see, that hopes to improve on intuitive reasoning based on intuitively valid inferences. Logical tautologies like P-->P aren't themselves considered to be true, they're only considered to represent truths, like 'if snow is white then snow is white', all of which is supposed to remind you that just because you dress something up in formalism doesn't mean you don't have to refer back to what you're trying to represent in the first place, which may be mundane in the sense of 'everyday'.
So of course you can call happiness a terminal value. Your values aren't constructed by your utility function; they're described by it. In my opinion you're taking things backward. Or, if maximal utility doesn't include increased happiness, you're doing it wrong, assuming happiness is what you value.
[Note: was edited.]
Replies from: Logos01↑ comment by Logos01 · 2012-04-25T06:26:42.463Z · LW(p) · GW(p)
So of course you can call happiness a terminal value.
I can call my cat a Harrier Jet, too. Doesn't mean she's going to start launching missiles from under the wings she doesn't have.
Or, if maximal utility doesn't include increased happiness, you're doing it wrong, assuming happiness is what you value.
You're confusing abitrary with intrinsic. To qualify as a terminal value a thing must be self-evidently valuable; that is, it must be inherently 'good'. More of it must always be 'better' than less of it. I know this to be false of happiness/pleasure; I know that there is such a thing as "too happy".
I know of no such thing as "too useful".
Replies from: adamisom↑ comment by adamisom · 2012-04-25T06:32:03.994Z · LW(p) · GW(p)
I think you're still missing the point. You can call happiness a terminal value, because you decide what those are.
I think you are confused here; what do you mean by inherently 'good'? Why must more of X always be better than less for? Does this resolve it?: yes, happiness =/= utility. I never claimed it was and I don't think anyone did. But among all the things that, when aggregated = your 'utility function', happiness (for most people) is a pretty big thing. And it is aggregate utility, and only aggregate utility, that would always be better with more.
Then, I suppose happiness isn't a terminal value. I think I was wrong. The only "terminal" value would be total utility.... but happiness is so fundamental and "self-evidently valuable" to most people that it seems useful to call such thing a "terminal value" if indeed you're going to call anything that.
P.S. I think you think you're saying something meaningful when you say "useful". I don't think you are. I think you're just expressing the idea of an aggregate utility, the sum. If not, what do you mean?
EDIT: This threw me for a loop: "I know this to be false of happiness/pleasure; I know that there is such a thing as "too happy"." Obviously, if happiness is a terminal value, you're right you can't be too happy. I think I'm either confused or tired or both. And if it so happens that in reality people don't desire, upon reflection, to maximize happiness because there's a point at which it's bad, then I understand you; such a person would be inconsistent to call happiness a terminal value in such a case.
Why do you think you can have too much happiness? (Think of some situation.)
Presumably there's some trade-off.....
Now consider someone else in that same situation. Would someone else also think they have too much happiness in that situation? Because if that's not the case, you just have different terminal values.
Ultimately, someone may judge their happiness to be most important to them. You can say, 'no, they should care more about (whatever tradeoff you think there is, maybe decreased ambition)'; they can simply respond, 'no, I disagree, I don't care more about that, I care more about happiness', because that's what it means for a value to be "terminal": it means for that value to the ultimate basis of judgment.
To make it clearer: you seem to think that different people's terminal values must be the same. Why do you think this?
Replies from: Logos01↑ comment by Logos01 · 2012-04-25T07:11:56.554Z · LW(p) · GW(p)
I think you're still missing the point.
Which is funny, because I am increasingly coming to the same conclusion with regards to your integration of my statements as you respond to me with essentially the same "talking points" in a manner that shows you haven't contemplated that at the very least merely repeating yourself isn't going to cause me to consider your old point any more relevant than it was the first time I offerred a rebuttal with new informational value.
At some point, I have learned that in such dialogues the only productive thing left for me to do is to simply drop the microphone and walk off the stage. I don't think this dialogue has quite reached that stage just yet. :)
You can call happiness a terminal value, because you decide what those are.
A rose by any other name. My pet; a harrier jet.
Declaring a thing to be another thing does not make it that thing. Brute fiat is insufficient to normative evaluations of intrinsic worth.
Obviously, if happiness is a terminal value, you're right you can't be too happy.
You somehow read the exact opposite of my meaning from my statement.
Also -- if you accept the notion of wireheading as an existential failure, then you acknowledge that happiness is not an intrinsic value.
Replies from: adamisom↑ comment by adamisom · 2012-04-25T07:23:17.267Z · LW(p) · GW(p)
Good point. And I think I'll have to exit too, because I have the feeling that I'm doing something wrong, and I'm frankly too tired to figure that out right now.
Just one question. "Declaring a thing to be another thing does not make it that thing. Brute fiat is insufficient to normative evaluations of intrinsic worth." Among other things I may be confused about, I'm (still) confused what intrinsic worth might be. Since I don't (currently) think 'intrinsic worth' is a thing, it seems to me that it is just the nature of a terminal value that it's something you choose, so I don't see the violation.
EDIT: Edited statement edited out.
Replies from: Logos01↑ comment by Logos01 · 2012-04-25T07:38:09.134Z · LW(p) · GW(p)
intrinsic values are values that a thing has merely by being what it is.
My question from the outset was "what's the use of happiness?" Responding to that with "its own sake" doesn't answer my question. To say that 'being useful is useful for its own sake' is to make an intrinsic utilitity statement of utility.
We -- or rather I -- framed this question in terms of utility from the outset.
Now -- hedonism is the default consensus view here on LessWrong.com. (obviously I am a dissenter. My personal history as being clinically anhedonic maaaaay have something to do with this.) the argument is made by hedonistic utilitarians that pleasure is the "measure of utility". That is; utility is pleasure; pleasure is utility.
But of course it's trivially easy to demonstrate the paucity of this reasoning -- we need only look to the wireheading existential failure mode, and other variations of it, to acknowledge that pleasure for pleasure's own sake is not an intrinsic value.
Without having intrinsic value, a value cannot be a terminal value; the terms are synonymous.
Since I don't (currently) think 'intrinsic worth' is a thing,
The position you are here aligning with is called "intrinsic nihilism". It claims that there are zero terminal/intrinsic goods. Now -- there's nothing wrong with that, from the outside view.
But it does leave us at something of an impasse; how could you then justify seeking happiness? If there are no intrinsic goods then your goals are entirely arbitrary. Which means that you must have reasoning for continuing to seek them out -- otherwise you would not continue to retain those arbitrary goals.
Absolutely -- our evolutionary history plays into this. But then, our evolutionary history includes rapine and slaughter. And we curttail that in lieu of creating a better society. So why does 'happiness' get a free pass from this inspection?
Replies from: nshepperd, Swimmer963, adamisom↑ comment by nshepperd · 2012-04-25T14:01:53.851Z · LW(p) · GW(p)
Now -- hedonism is the default consensus view here on LessWrong.com.
What? Really?
(I'm thinking of this and this.)
Replies from: TheOtherDave, Logos01↑ comment by TheOtherDave · 2012-04-25T14:22:04.412Z · LW(p) · GW(p)
No, not really.
Or, at least, not obviously.
I can see making an argument that most LW users implicitly adopt a hedonistic model when thinking about stuff-people-value, even if they would explicitly reject such a model. I'm not sure that's true, but I'm not sure it's false either; certainly I find myself doing that sometimes when I don't pay attention. I don't think that's sufficient justification to declare hedonism a local consensus, but I suppose one could probably make that argument as well.
↑ comment by Logos01 · 2012-04-25T20:12:38.544Z · LW(p) · GW(p)
(I'm thinking of this and this.)
Eudaimonic hedonism is still a form of hedonism.
(EDIT: Specifically it's epicurian as compared to cyrenaic.)
Replies from: thomblake, nshepperd↑ comment by thomblake · 2012-04-25T20:28:59.998Z · LW(p) · GW(p)
Eudaimonic hedonism is still a form of hedonism.
That seems entirely wrong. In fact, I think "eudaimonic hedonism" is just a contradiction in terms. Normally eudaimonic well-being is contrasted with hedonistic well-being.
ETA: Maybe you were thinking, "Eudaimonist utlitiarianism is still a form of utilitarianism"?
Replies from: Logos01↑ comment by Logos01 · 2012-04-25T22:34:52.264Z · LW(p) · GW(p)
Maybe you were thinking [...]
I meant what I said. Eudaimonic hedonism is still a form of hedonism. Eudaimonia is simply redefined happiness.
It is contrasted with "traditional" hedonism in common usage, but the relationship is quite clear. Eudaimonia is not a rejection of traditional hedonism but a modification.
Replies from: thomblake↑ comment by thomblake · 2012-04-25T22:54:20.411Z · LW(p) · GW(p)
Definitely just mincing words here, but...
Hedonism and eudaimonia can both be considered types of 'happiness' - thus we talk about "hedonic well-being" and "eudaimonic well-being", and we can construe both as ways of talking about 'happiness'. But it's a misconstrual of eudaimonia to think it reduces to pleasure, and a misuse of 'hedonism' to refer to goals other than pleasure.
Replies from: Logos01↑ comment by Logos01 · 2012-04-26T00:17:41.273Z · LW(p) · GW(p)
But it's a misconstrual of eudaimonia to think it reduces to pleasure, and a misuse of 'hedonism' to refer to goals other than pleasure.
This is simply not true. Eudaimonia is essentially epicurian hedonism, as contrasted with cyrenaic.
Replies from: TimS, thomblake↑ comment by TimS · 2012-04-26T00:42:16.778Z · LW(p) · GW(p)
Looking only at the wiki page, epicurian moral thought doesn't look like what I remember from reading Aristotle's Ethics. But it's been a while.
↑ comment by thomblake · 2012-04-26T15:09:24.830Z · LW(p) · GW(p)
Eudaimonia is essentially epicurian hedonism, as contrasted with cyrenaic.
I think we're better to follow Aristotle than Epicurus in defining eudaimonia. It's at least the primary way the word is used now. Being a good human is just not a sort of pleasure.
↑ comment by nshepperd · 2012-04-26T06:55:17.459Z · LW(p) · GW(p)
I see. Then you do not mean that
pleasure is the "measure of utility". That is; utility is pleasure; pleasure is utility.
is the consensus view here at LW. Since after all, the consensus view here is that wireheading is a bad idea.
Replies from: Logos01↑ comment by Logos01 · 2012-04-26T07:39:24.498Z · LW(p) · GW(p)
Then you do not mean that
pleasure is the "measure of utility". That is; utility is pleasure; pleasure is utility.
Eudaimonic pleasure -- happiness -- is of a nature that wireheading would not qualify as valid happiness/pleasure. It would be like 'empty calories'; tasty but unfulfilling.
So no, I do not not mean that 'pleasure is the "measure of utility"' is the mainstream consensus view on LessWrong. I do mean that, and I believe it to be so. "Hedons" and "utilons" are used interchangeably here.
Replies from: nshepperd↑ comment by Swimmer963 (Miranda Dixon-Luinenburg) (Swimmer963) · 2012-04-25T14:18:27.306Z · LW(p) · GW(p)
My question from the outset was "what's the use of happiness?" Responding to that with "its own sake" doesn't answer my question. To say that 'being useful is useful for its own sake' is to make an intrinsic utilitity statement of utility.
My answer to this would be that happiness doesn't necessarily have any value outside of human brains. But that doesn't matter. For most people, it's one of those facets of life that is so basic, so integrated into everything, that it's impossible not to base a lot of decisions on "what makes me happy." (And variants: what makes me satisfied with myself, what makes me able to be proud of myself...I would consider these metrics to be happiness-based even if they don't measure just pleasure in the moment.)
You can try to make general unified theories about what should be true, but in the end, what is true is that human brains experience a state called happiness, and it's a state most people like and want, and that doesn't change no matter what your theory is.
↑ comment by adamisom · 2012-04-25T07:51:26.305Z · LW(p) · GW(p)
Thanks for the link. Of course I should have checked that....
I'd like to point out that you find this in the second paragraph: "For an eudaemonist, happiness has intrinsic value"
Given the rest of what you've said, and my attachment to happiness as self-evidently valuable, a broader conception of "happiness" (as in eudamonia above) may avoid adverse outcomes like wireheading (assuming it is one). As other commenters here have noted there is no single definition anyway. You might say the broader it becomes, the less useful. Sure, but any measure would probably have to be really broad--like "utility". When I said I don't think 'intrinsic worth' is a thing, it's because I was identifying it with utility, and... I guess I wasn't thinking of (overall) utility as a 'thing' because to me, the concept is really vague and I just think of it an aggregate. An aggregate of things like happiness that contribute to utility.
I mentioned how if you're going to call anything a terminal value, happiness seems like a good one. Now I don't think so: you seem to be saying that you shouldn't (edit: aren't justified in considering) anything a terminal value other than utility itself, which seems reasonable. Is that right?
More to the point:
So why does 'happiness' get a free pass from this inspection?
I'm not sure; it now seems to me it oughtn't to. Maybe another Less Wronger can contribute more, though not me.
Replies from: adamisom↑ comment by wedrifid · 2012-04-25T03:46:27.735Z · LW(p) · GW(p)
This is nonsensical. Do we always conform to patterns merely because they're the patterns we always adhered to, unquestioningly? The question is being asked now.
Right now some people prefer happiness. Many of the people who prefer happiness also endorse desiring to be happy and as such they right now prefer not to self modify away from desiring happiness.
then what justifies this article?
No justification is required for preferring one's preferences. That's the default. If you keep asking "Why?" enough you are bound to end up at the bottom level terminal goals from which other instrumental goals may be derived. Agents don't need to justify having terminal goals to you.
Replies from: Logos01↑ comment by Logos01 · 2012-04-25T06:20:50.713Z · LW(p) · GW(p)
Right now some people prefer happiness.
This is handwaving. That is; you use a description to fulfill the role of an explanation.
Many of the people who prefer happiness also endorse desiring to be happy
This is also a description, not an explanation.
No justification is required for preferring one's preferences.
... I cannot help but find this to be a silly assertion. "That's the default"? That's just... not true.
f you keep asking "Why?" enough you are bound to end up at the bottom level terminal goals from which other instrumental goals may be derived.
Absolutely. And those terminal goals are those which are intrinsic in nature.
If you are claiming that happiness is an intrinsic good -- please, explain why. Because I for one just don't see it.
Replies from: aleksiL↑ comment by aleksiL · 2012-05-03T15:51:42.997Z · LW(p) · GW(p)
It seems to me as if you view terminal goals as universal, not mind-specific. Is this correct, or have I misunderstood?
The point, as I understand it, that some humans seem to have happiness as a terminal goal. If you truly do not share this goal, then there is nothing left to explain. Value is in the mind, not inherent in the object it is evaluating. If one person values a thing for its own sake but another does not, this is a fact about their minds, not a disagreement about the properties of the thing.
Was this helpful?
comment by Hul-Gil · 2012-04-17T16:29:52.522Z · LW(p) · GW(p)
Great post! I'm going to use as much of it as I can.
I think it might be difficult to apply some of these, since I notice a good deal of my unhappiness is not affected by changes in thought or outward motions, and it can be hard to translate knowing you should try something into actually applying it. (But both of these can be mitigated: smiling, for instance, really does make me feel a bit happier even if I'm forcing the smile, and I'm sure there are plenty of articles about akrasia, here on LessWrong.)
Prefer experiential purchases; avoid materialistic goals.
Indeed. You can also skip the middleman and go straight to purchasing the direct experience of euphoria. The caveat of varying your experiences applies here too, though. Especially here.
comment by Michelle_Z · 2012-04-16T15:07:57.970Z · LW(p) · GW(p)
Overall, it is a good explanation supported by evidence, however I would like to see a followup with perhaps some different ways to implement that kind of thinking.
comment by [deleted] · 2016-02-10T13:15:24.181Z · LW(p) · GW(p)
Why did OP delete her account?
Replies from: entirelyuseless↑ comment by entirelyuseless · 2016-02-10T15:14:19.404Z · LW(p) · GW(p)
My understanding was that their username was recognizable by people who knew them in real life and they wanted to make sure that did not happen.
Replies from: gjm↑ comment by gjm · 2016-02-11T00:01:27.740Z · LW(p) · GW(p)
Looking at the comments, it looks to me as if the OP didn't delete their account -- there are multiple comments below, with username still attached, that appear to be by the OP. Is there a mechanism for deleting just the association between an account and a single post, or something?
Replies from: entirelyuseless↑ comment by entirelyuseless · 2016-02-11T03:50:20.477Z · LW(p) · GW(p)
I see many comments with [deleted] but none with the username, maybe you are looking at different comments. Or it could be the result of some error.
Replies from: gjm↑ comment by gjm · 2016-02-11T10:38:43.227Z · LW(p) · GW(p)
I see all of these comments as having an author (the same author). They all seem to me to be clearly by the OP.
Replies from: entirelyuseless↑ comment by entirelyuseless · 2016-02-11T16:57:50.536Z · LW(p) · GW(p)
Ok. I had assumed the main post was by someone else with a deleted account who appears in the comments. But it looks like you're right.
comment by [deleted] · 2016-02-08T12:24:03.912Z · LW(p) · GW(p)
It's hard to resolve this with my productivity (for effective altruism) goals.
comment by [deleted] · 2012-08-05T21:41:59.328Z · LW(p) · GW(p)
The following quote is misattributed to Ahuvia, (2002)
This research also supports the broaden-and-build theory of positive emotions by demonstrating that higher levels of happiness may expand an individual’s mindset to include thoughts of others.
The quote comes from Aknin, Dunn, & Norton, (2011a), p. 352.
Also, this post has been absurdly useful to me. Fantastic job! :)